NOTES / ROUGH SKETCH of Sociology of Law lecture

SKIM ONLY

(**NOTE**: Remember---these are only ROUGH LECTURE NOTES in prose form to make following lectures a bit easier. In lecture, I will update and tailor and add/delete as needed, so these are not only rough, but partial and incomplete) THE SOCIOLOGY OF LAW: A HISTORICAL PERSPECTIVE Jim Thomas Department of Sociology Northern Illinois University DeKalb, IL (60115) (started 15 January, 1997 - ongoing through 2008) 1. INTRODUCTION These comments are LECTURE NOTES, not a paper.t I have attempted to put together, in coherent form, the discussion of the first few weeks on the history of law. The course takes a historical perspective, and this paper lays out the fundamental ideas we will be discussing. PROLOGUE In recent years, law has become a battleground for competing ideas, ideologies, and shaping social issues such as civil rights, presidential elections, and culture itself. Terms such as "Nanny-gate," and "Borking" have been introduced into our cultural language as the result of bat- tles over confirmation of nominees to the US Supreme Court. Al- though ideologically partisan, the roots of the conflicts have a long history, and this is why we will address a few historical issues in this course. A historical perspective is especially useful because of the de- bates over the confirmation of US Supreme Court nominees in re- cent years. The basis of the debates lies on ideological grounds, especially as contained in the opposing perspectives of legal fundamentalism and "living law." There are two sub-issues in- volved. First, some observers claim that the president alone has the power and authority to appoint judges to the federal bench. Opponents claim that it is the right of the Senate, who, by con- stitutional directive, may oppose any appointment. Both views are correct. The Constitution says: He [the President] shall have power, by and with the advice and consent of the Senate, to make treaties, provided two-thirds of the Senators present concur; and he shall nominate, and by and with the advice and con- sent of the Senate, shall appoint ambassadors, other public ministers and consuls, judges of the Supreme Court, and all other officers of the United States, whose appointments are not herein otherwise provide for, and which shall be established by law: but the Congress may by law vest the appointment of such in- ferior officers, as they think proper, in the President alone, in the courts of law, or in the heads of depart- ments [U.S. Constitution, Article II, Section 2.2]. The language may seem clear, but the meanings of it are, in fact, complex and open to considerable room for debate. Some argue that the language explicitely allows the Senate to intervene and reject appointments they do not feel proper. Others disagree, and argue that the Senate is "changing the rules in the bottom of the ninth inning." By looking at the history of law, we can bet- ter understand both sides of this issue. The second sub-issue involves the nature of legal fundamentalism and the doctrine of original intents. The Reagan administration has strongly argued that federal judges should not "make law" by reading new meanings into the Constitution. Judges should, it is argued, rely on what the founders "really meant" or "really in- tended." Opponents of this view counter by arguing that the Con- stitution is a living document, and that judges, by the nature of our democracy, must develop new meanings to adjust old law to new situations. Both sides have some merit, but each can be examined within the context of the historical evolution of law to deter- mine which is most convincing[1]. By looking at the history of law, we can obtain a better under- standing of the issues involved, and clarify our own personal views. SOME PRELIMINARY ISSUES There are several themes we will address. of the relationship between social change and the form and content of law. By form, we mean what law is supposed to do, how it is practiced and ap- plied, the logic and structure of the rules, and the procedures that guide its application. By content, we mean what the law says, both as written in statutes and as developed through case law (judicial decisions). Too many people think of the law as "simply there," as something more or less permanent, and some- thing that is "sacred." However, societies change and laws change with them. The concept of "civil rights" is historically recent, and changing social definitions of this concept have required considerable legal change, both in what laws say and in how law is applied. A second issue is that of law as a normative system. For some scholars, laws reflect social consensus, or agreement by most citizens on how people and government should behave. For others, especially Marxists and conflict theorists, laws reflect not har- mony and agreement, but rather symbolize disagreements and social conflict. This, these theorists argue, is why we need law: To re- solve disagreements that cannot be resolved through other means. By a normative system, we mean the sum of the values, traditions, customs, mores and folkways (and, of course, laws) that guide be- havior and provide sanctions (rewards or punishments) for obeying and violating expectations. We often are able to recognize how traditions and values change, but are not as able to recognize how law should or does accommodate these changes. For example, in the past century, the traditional role of women has changed, and the former values that shaped women's roles have also changed. Yet, many observers suggest that law, especially consti- tutional law, should not necessarily reflect these changes, be- cause it is the domain of the states, not the federal government, that is most responsible for such accommodation. A third issue underlying the social bases of law is that of ideology. Law reflects social ideals, distribution of political power, and above all, a "proper order of things." These are all tied to fundamental concepts that various groups think are impor- tant for a smoothly running society. By examining the relation- ship between ideology and law, we can better understand the com- peting views on the role of law in society. A fourth issue, that of the relationship between law and the state, is important for examining how social power has shifted from states to the federal government in the past century. This shift has not occurred overnight, and it has not occurred simply because "liberal" judge have engaged in judicial activism. It has occurred because of complex changes in society, including the growth of business, the recognition that some groups have been dispossessed of rights, the increasing homogeneity of culture, and other factors that create social conflict. The federal gov- ernment has assumed more responsibility for resolving these ten- sions, and law has been one strategy by which it is done. A final issue is that of social practice. Law does not exist in a vacuum, but is the product of people creating a social order to their liking. As a social product, law is a form of human activ- ity by which conflicts over social power and resources are fought, and through which previously disempowered groups attempt to resolve problems or attain rights. As a consequence, we can- not understand the relationship between law and society without understanding the role of human activity as the fount of law. A COMMENT ON IDEOLOGY We have argued that any view of law reflects an ideology. It is therefore useful to briefly define what an ideology is. Definition of Ideology An ideology refers to those beliefs, attitudes, and basic assump- tions about the world that justify, shape and organize how we perceive and interpret the world. An ideology underlies norms, laws and values. It is a set of the most-basic assumptions and rationalizatons about our social world. Examples include the be- lieve in "justice for all," which guides the criminal justice system; "one person one vote," "my country right or wrong" and "equal opportunity," which guide our political process; "women should not receive equal pay for equal work," or "women do not belong in grad school taking up slots men should have," which guides gender relations; "free enterprise," which guides our eco- nomic system, and other beliefs by which we defend "what is." An ideology provides the basic framework for decisions and policies about the social world and political activity. more specifical- ly, ideologies are the conceptual machineries for maintaining so- cial order. Ideology, as Marx suggests, reflects a "false" or "distorted" consciousness in that it prevents us from seeing the world as it "really is" in that we do not question that which we accept as "normal." The trick is to identify the ideological constraints that block our understandings of the world. Ideologies tend to be views of the world, but they are partial and incomplete, not because they are necessarily wrong, but be- cause of the questions that we do not ask. We seldom, if ever, question our beliefs and assumptions about the nature of the world or the social order which ideologies sustain and preserve. This is what we mean by "distorted"--they may be appropriate for a given social order or historical period, but they do not ade- quately portray the actual social relations that exist. Ideolo- gies create and generate the ideas, concepts, etc, appropriate to our social world, and also LEGITIMIZE and promote particular con- ceptions of the way things OUGHT to be. Ideologies have several features: 1. They are PRECONSCIOUS 2. They are emotionally charged 3. They are shared among a large group of individuals; (ie, are NOT simply individual attitudes, but SOCIAL con- structs) 4. They contain assumptions about the state of the world and how it OUGHT TO BE 5. They are DISTORTED pictures because they are limited and partial (and they thus generate "false consciousness" be- cause they are incomplete. The functions of ideologies include, but are certainly not limit- ed to the following: 1. Justifying the status quo 2. They guide the activity and policy of a particular group (eg, the state, legislature, judiciary, etc) 3. They maintain the dominant position of those who are able to 'Name the world." 4. Ideologies are one form of noncoercive social control. There are different ways to control people. We can do it by a) force (inappropriate for most things) or b) by con- trolling symbols. IDEOLOGY IS THUS A WAY OF CONTROLLING WITHOUT VIOLENCE OR COERCION. This may seem like common sense, but it is one thing to recognize that control ex- ists, and quite another to demonstrate how it operates, in whose interests, and how it can be addressed through so- cial policy. In short, ideology guides and shapes and justifies our practices. To understand social inquiry, it is thus useful to first under- stand the role ideologies play in blocking our vision of society. In short, ideologies contain the major conceptions and the sym- bols accumulated in our culture, and represent views of social order, right and wrong and identify who should or should not be subject to control, processing, and punishment. We discuss ideology for several reasons: 1. It helps us understand the complex nature of social control (it's easier to control behavior by controlling ideas). 2. It helps illustrates contradictions and tensions in socie- ty (for example, between opposites, such as gun control/ anti-gun control; right-to-life/right to choose; Death penalty/anti-death penalty). 3. Iit illustrates how the state functions to manufacture ways of seeing and talking about the social world (ie, it presents accounts and rationales to legitimize actions, such as intervention in state affairs, protecting rights. 4. It helps helps us guide our analysis of society and helps set strategies for SOCIAL POLICY. Most simply, ideologies are one of the most fundamental aspects in the relationship between law and society, for it not only shapes our view of law, but also shapes how we live within a sys- tem of laws. A HISTORICAL SUMMARY Our discussion begins with English law, but, obviously, law in both written and unwritten form has existed for many thousands of years. To provide a background to the emergence of English law, a short discussion of the pre-English roots might be helpful. The Emergence of Law Law is one of many element shaping human behavior, and it mobi- lizes the force of organized society to regulate individual and group conduct to prevent, redress or punish deviations from pre- scribed social norms. Law's purpose is to mold individual behav- ior in accordance with pre-established patterns imposed by indi- viduals who play the role of "authority." Do societies need laws? When people can't agree on essentials, or if they can't trust each other, they may put rules and rela- tionships into writing, and make use of or create formal institu- tions (courts, special division of labor, police, arbitrators). This formality changes how people relate to each other. For ex- ample, what, for U.S. citizens, becomes a domestic dispute in- volving police in a situation of extreme domestic violence, may in some societies, such as China, be a matter for neighborhood arbitration committees. In any society, laws, as we define them, possess several charac- teristics. First, laws contain symbols. Laws symbolize "correct- ness," norms, values, traditions, power hierarchies, and other social attributes. Second, they must be codified, or "made per- manent," in some fashion, usually through writing. Third, there must exist a method of enforcement. These can include police, "magic," social pressure, or some other force that enables socie- ty to punish or reward members. Fourth, there must be something to enforce, such as a behavior ("thou shalt not kill") or a so- cial group (tall people cannot live in this city). Finally, there must, obviously, be something specific to be enforced. Laws are not general, but specific. In this form, laws have been with us for several thousand years. Ancient Law Hammurabi. The concept of personal justice is visible in all early laws, and most historians, for convenience, data the begin- ning of law to Hammurabi, a Babylonian king (circa 1,800 b.c.). Hammurabi inherited a large territory from his father, and to simply its administration, he codified (wrote down) the existing norms and practices of the time. He did not create new laws, but simply pulled together those rules that already existed. His codes added much to our knowledge of law in the ancient near east during this period and shed light on the later codes (e.g., new testament derived from these), indicating that our legal ideas have much in common with a broader foundation handed down many millenniums ago. The basic model, or theory, of justice in Ham- murabi's system was lex talionus, or "an eye for an eye." In this model of personal justice, an offender was punished by submitting to a punishment roughly comparable to the original offense. This did not necessarily mean that the offender would under the exact same fate as he or she perpetrated, but rather "values" were place on offenses that were considered comparable. For example, if you stole a neighbor's cow, you would have to replace it, but if you were responsible for the accidental death of another, you would not necessarily be killed, but might lose a hand. The Code of Hammurabi is first comprehensive legal document that has come down to us virtually intact, although it appeared sever- al centuries after that of Ur-Nammu, a Summerian king, whose laws are the most ancient discovered to date. Hammurabi's laws re- flect the importance of rich agricultural traditions in ancient Babylonia and how social structure is entwined with it. Biblical Law. Biblical law (or Mosaic law, because it was "hand- ed down by Moses"), was based on vengeance and retribution. For example, a man falsely accusing his wife of being a non-virgin would be whipped, but if the woman was not a virgin when wedded, she was to be stoned to death. Pre-marital sex, in fact, was, in most cases, punishable by death (Deuteronomy, 22:13-22-28). Mo- saic law included 36 capital crimes, punishable by any one of four methods of death: stoning, burning, decapitation or strangu- lation. Hebrews drew no real distinction between religious and secular norms---the two types were formally identical (e.g, all laws came from God, and if punishments followed the prescribed format laid out by Moses' summary, then justice was served. There were punishments, equally harsh by today's standards, for other offenses, and some groups retain the view that the literal interpretation of social responses to crime is preferred over more recent ones. It should be remembered that Mosaic law reflected what Durkheim would call a mechanism for integrating diverse tribes into a com- mon group, and many of the rules were centered around strategies to maintain social cohesion and common practices. In exile and subject to the power of other nations, Jews inevitably had to re- ly heavily upon group pressure and threats of supernatural sanc- tions to gain conformity to edicts. The fundamental premise of Hebrew jurisprudence was that the revealed will of god was the sole source of legislation. Consequently, every punishable act constituted a violation of god's will, and every offense is termed in the Talmud "Aberrh," meaning a transgression against God. In this system, offenses were neither against the individu- al nor against society, but against a supernatural being who com- manded vengeance. But this slowly changed as the Greek system, which heavily influenced our own, evolved. Greece and Rome (1,200 to 300 b.c.) Our own law has been shaped by Ancient law, but these laws took many forms and emerged gradually over several thousand years. The Homeric Era. In The Illiad and The Odyssey, Homer provides partial insights into "norm enforcement." Criminal procedures were relatively primitive, and the blood feud, a system in which wrongs were avenged by the victim's family, provided the primary mechanism for punishment of major offenders. In The Illiad, for example, when Agamemnon's wife, Helen, was kidnapped by Paris and taken to Troy, Agamemnon enlisted his family, friends, neighbors and allies to avenge the crime. Paris' act was not considered a wrong against Agamemnon's kingdom or against society, but an act against an individual, and it was the responsibility of the indi- vidual to avenge it. Although this was a dramatic example, it provides insights into the relationship between offense and so- cial control. Families were expected to respond to wrongs against individual members, usually "in kind, plus,"[2] and, in principal, the matter was resolved. But this led to problems, es- pecially when an offender claimed innocence, and vengeance was sought anyway. For this reason, blood feuds were often, as the name implies, quite bloody, and could last for many years, either until families were too drained to continue, or until there were no family members remaining who wished to pursue the feud. Al- though this system of justice is not common to the U.S., there are examples of members of other cultures continuing a feud in this country that was begun in their own. An example occurred in Detroit, where police arrested a man for murder who claimed he was simply avenging a wrong done to a family member. He could not understand why he was being prosecuted. Obviously, this system of justice could be disruptive to the so- cial fabric. Valuable laborers were killed or maimed, economic productivity was channeled into vengeance rather than more useful outlets, social affairs were disrupted, and normal life for some families on occasion ceased. It was left to Solon (circa 594 b.c.) to end the system. Solon. Solon was a King in Athens in the late sixth century. He was also called "The Law Giver," because he reformed the existing system of justice. He rewrote laws so that they "made sense," tried to establish a uniform method of application, and above all, he declared an end to the blood feud. In addition, he in- troduced several new procedures of justice. One of the most im- portant of these was the procedure in which an offended party could appeal to the state for resolution. More simply, Solon es- tablished the right of Athenians to prosecute other citizens. Law was slowly evolving from a crime against an individual or group that required response from that group, but a crime against the state. Solon was not completely successful in his reforms. For example, the blood feud, although dramatically curtailed, did on occasion persist. The notion of "crime against the state" was not yet ful- ly developed, and the system depended largely on the ability of a single "wise counsellor," the king, to resolve complaints. There was, as yet, no adequate formal mechanism for processing com- plaints. Nonetheless, the recognition that law, rather than naked force, was useful in maintaining social stability was es- tablished. One of the most important consequences of this period was the emphasis put on the philosophical discussions of abstract principles of law. This occurred especially during the Hellenis- tic period. Roman Law. Roman law begins with the Code (or Twelve Tables), which date from the 5th century b.c. These were not systematic statements of law, but a summary of customary norms. As with Hammurabi, didn't give laws, but reflected existing expectations and traditions. Roman law evolved over nearly 1,000 years (about 300 bc to 500 a.d.) and was heavily influenced by Greek tradi- tions. At first Roman law was primarily restitutive (eg, law primarily used to determine compensation for offenses. This is significant, because a "crime" was seen as and act between indi- viduals, not as an offense against the state. which required Of- fenses required mediation, because offenses were situational, and punishments could not be applied literally by following a rigid list of appropriate responses. Instead, aggrieved parties and offenders had to be called before a magistrate and both sides heard, then evaluated, and only then could the punishment be as- sessed in the context of the behavior. In Rome, the first true "legal profession" gradually developed (circa second century a.d.), and Roman jurists began writing texts and commentaries on particular laws and also worked with legal concepts, much as they do today. The Justinian Codes. By the sixth century a.d., both the content and practice of law had evolved into a complex system. This was in part the influence of the Church, that had developed a sophis- ticated administration and set of procedural rules, and because of the Roman tradition (that, of course, influenced the struc- ture, although not the content, of ecclesiastical (or Church) law. The emperor Justinian recognized the unweildy set of laws, many of which were contradictory, and the difficult practices of implementing them, so he set about to reform both the letter and application of his legal system. His laws attempted to combine aspects of ancient law with the Roman system, but his ideas re- quired a cumbersome bureaucracy to make it operate.but required a cumbersome bureaucracy---Some of the features of his law includ- ed: 1. An attempt to establish scales of justice and fairness. 2. The belief that a crime and its punishment must be bal- anced. 3. The view that law was universal, and had to applied equal- ly to all cases without the penetration of biased discre- tion of officials. 4. The recognition that law requires an "official apparatus," not simply a number of skilled practitioners or wise coun- sellors, if it is to be consistently effective over a long period of time. 5. The emphasis on a specialized division of specialized la- bor responsible for implementing the various administra- tive tasks required for the legal process. The Justinian Codes did not survive the demise of Rome, but they did creep back into the laws of western Europe over the next few centuries, especially in the Germanic kingdoms and especially in the English system. However, by the middle ages, laws were a me- lange of Roman and home-spun elements. Law changes slowly, and we are often unable to recognize the fac- tors that shape our own justice system. Because our own philoso- phies and procedures have been significantly shaped by Judaic, Greek and Roman law, it may be easier to understand how our own system itself is in a state of continual, albeit gradual, tran- sition. SUMMARY The purpose of this introduction has been to show that there are many issues underlying the relationship between law and society, and that by understanding the history of law, it is easier to view this relationship. Our own legal system can be traced both procedurally and philosophically back at least to ancient Greece, but the more recent roots are found in English law. We now turn to these roots. One final comment. There are references throughout to civil rights litigation by prisoners, which is a theme I use for exam- ples. This will be explained periodically in class. Briefly, prisoner litigation are those suits filed by people in correc- tional facilities that challenge the conditions of existence. This topic provides a useful set of examples, because it raises questions of judicial domain, judicial review, states' rights, changing concepts of law, social control, and other factors un- derlying the transformation of legal principles and ideology. 2. THE ENGLISH LEGACY AND ITS SOCIAL ROOTS: 500-1214 The greatest of all legal fictions is that the law it- self evolves, from case to case, by its own impartial logic, true only to its own integrity, unswayed by ex- pedient considerations (Thompson, 1975: 250). Law, to borrow a metaphor from the seventeenth century jurist Sir Matthew Hale (1971: 40), is like Jason's ship the Argos. Al- though it appeared upon return the same as when it departed, dur- ing its long voyage virtually every part was replaced. Thus, de- spite the appearance of sameness, changes altered its essence. Law, too, is continually changing, such that we often fail to recognize that, despite the illusion of permanency, it is contin- ually transformed by powerful social forces that inexorably modi- fy both its form and content. Thus, although our contemporary system of laws and procedures may appear to conform to some in- ternally consistent logic or to be derived from established prin- ciples, the structural relations on which it is based are contin- ually in flux, and the concepts of freedom, equality, protection of property and due process are changing also. Ignoring our his- torical antecedents contributes to the perception of ours as an immutable legal structure, thus preventing us from understanding the expansion of, for example, existing rights to persons who were previously unprotected. As a consequence, we often fail to recognize the processes of change in our own system, and our judgments and subsequent judicial policies thus become misdirect- ed, misunderstood, or simply misplaced. Nowhere is this more ev- ident than in interpretations of the relationship between federal judges and the U.S. Constitution. Especially since the mid-1960s, critics have observed an "erosion" of fundamental Con- stitutional principles by activist judges who would rather "set policy" than interpret established law (Bork, 1971; Duscha, 1969; Morgan, 1984; Meese, 1985, 1986). This view, however, glosses over the latent "living law" aspect of our judicial system which allows for, and in fact requires periodic judicial revision or rejection of statute law in light of changing social, political, or ideological practices. By ignoring our historical roots we also tend to ignore the commonality that the U.S. system shares with the English legal tradition dating back a millennium. At stake in the debates over legal fundamentalism are the con- cepts of judicial review, the weight of common law, and how these and related legal concepts change. Judicial review, for example, has referred historically to the power of a court to decide the scope of authority of specific legislation or court decisions. These common law roots of judicial review, however, have been radically modified, and now provide judicial authority to review both law and activities under "color of law" if they conflict with broader, more fundamental legal norms or philosophy (Schmeiser, 1965: 22). This latter view is the basis of current civil rights litigation, and provides as well the authority for federal courts to monitor and intervene in prison administration, criminal procedures, hiring practices, university policies or church-state issues. Much of the current debate over the legiti- macy of courts to intervene in state affairs also depends on whether one subscribes to a common law or "living law" concept of the Constitution. Those adhering to common law, or "antiquarian- ism," argue that past precedents ought to be the basis of current decisions stare decisis. In this view, primacy is given to the stability of law established by the "test of time" thesis, which holds that only those decisions which are sound will last and therefore should be employed to guide current judicial decisions. In this view, courts have violated the centuries-long tradition of "hands off" in prison cases, thus violating the intents of the framers of the Constitution and its foundations in common law. Those advocating the living-law perspective opt for the primacy of contemporary needs over "archaic decisions." In this view, it is the spirit, rather than the letter of the law, that is granted primacy, and prior decisions only provide guidelines, rather than immutable precedents. These advocates tacitly advocate the Sa- trean view that the source of law lies in social dynamics rather than in an abstract and autonomous past, and that it may occa- sionally be necessary to use the law as a weapon in social change to assure that the principle of justice is met. This work reflects the perspective of living law, and it is or- ganized around the theme that social, political, or economic crises and the accompanying attempts at resolution precede legal changes by creating new legal definitions and new administrative mechanisms to address them. It describes the socio-legal context of prisoner litigation, and the corresponding legal changes which have shaped even such a narrow phenomenon as prisoner litigation. A historical approach is crucial in order to test the dominant view that the contemporary definition of rights and their exten- sion to new categories of persons emerges from either "incorrect" ideological thinking or judicial miscarriages. Historical de- scriptions are thus useful because they place distance between ourselves and the immediacy of the present, thereby allowing us to see familiar objects in a new light. The history of prisoner litigation, for example, is not so much the history of correc- tions or offenders as it is of the role of the law and courts, the increasing importance given to the judiciary in settling dis- putes, legislation creating and defining new rights and extending legal protections to new categories of legal subjects, and above all, changing interpretations of the Constitution. Prisoner lit- igation, because of the emotional and ideologically-based nature of its subject matter, is especially vulnerable to judgments clouded by fact and reason. Tracing its historical roots should demonstrate that prisoner litigation is one of many facets of our system of jurisprudence that can be linked to a millennium of le- gal and administrative changes. The history of law is the history of attempts by state authority to resolve through legal means those disputes for which alterna- tives are not viable. Struggles over who benefits or loses, who possesses legal rights and who does not, which laws shall be en- acted and enforced, and what role law shall play in maintaining social and political order further add to the conflictual nature of law. Law cannot be defined simply as enacted statutes, but includes as well existing policies and procedures of enforcement, tacit social understandings about rights and obligations, and the entire administrative edifice by which law is done. It has its genesis and consequences in such factors as centralization of ad- ministration and the rise of the nation state, as well as in eco- nomic, political, religious, and other social factors that create new definitions of "rights" as well as new groups who enjoy them. In short, the rise of law has occurred largely as a mechanism for mediating existing power arrangements. It is not simply by leg- islation or judicial decisions that law has grown, but rather through shifting social forces for which existing forms of admin- istrative conflict resolution are no longer appropriate. Briefly tracing the development of English law from pre-Norman England through the seventeenth century will help illustrate the roots of our own system. Identifying the more salient social factors out of which our system emerged will serve to show how it, too, is subject to many of the same pressures that have shaped both the form and content of legal substance and procedure. PRE-NORMAN ENGLAND English written law dates at least to the mid-seventh century. Despite nearly 500 years of Romanization, which began in 54 b.c., Roman jurisprudence did not survive into sixth century England. Through the Church, however, the tradition of Roman law did not disappear completely, despite English social disintegration and reorganization following the Empire's collapse. By 407, the Ro- mans were no longer a force in England, and the church in Europe was demanding independence, even dominance, over the state. In 410, Honorious instructed British towns to provide for their own defense, and when Constantine III was defeated and killed in 412, Rome was too weak to regain the lost British provinces, and they began to form their own distinctive culture (Collingwood, 1949: 47). The two centuries prior to the beginning of the seventh century were years of Saxon colonization in east-central England, and Saxon cultural influences included language, political organ- ization, and a rich oral tradition. Although some European rul- ers (notably Theodosius II and Euric) had issued statute books, in England this did not occur. Following the Saxon invasion, English law evolved from the Teu- tonic custom into which Roman tradition had been slowly filtering through the Dark Ages, and feudal law still bore traces of its double origin in the system of the Teutonic "comitatus" and of the Roman "beneficium." Nonetheless, although much of the essen- tial legal structure was Saxon, the subsequent development was purely English. Canon law had been developed out of customs and precedents which had served to regulate the first Christian com- munities and which had been largely formed from the civil law of Rome. Disparate local customs were preserved by the jealousies that prevailed between one village or manor and another because of both the strong sense of local life and jurisdiction, and the strict adherence to long-standing traditions (Green, 1968: 113). The Anglo-Saxon law that emerged has been called "an especially pure type of Germanic archaism" (Pollack and Maitland, 1968: 44), influenced especially by such concepts and institutions as the witan (king's council), wer (designated fees to be paid to the victim for offense), and wite (penalty or fine) are Germanic in origin. The gemot, a court or assembly empowered to hear cases, was a general term used for the king's witan as well as for local bodies. There was no truly central administration other than the church, and the Saxon king's role remained that of dispenser of court privilege rather than legal administrator. In a second wave of colonization, the Danes had established settlements and assimilated in about three-quarters of the country by the end of the ninth century, and these three distinct cultures, Danish, Sa- xon and Briton, combined to create a form of social organization and legal relations peculiar to England. As on the continent, at the close of the first millennium, Eng- land was a feudal[3] which here refers to . . .a series of tiny economic nodules whose population and productivity were slowly increasing, and in which the legal mechanisms ensured that the bulk of the sur- plus went to the landlords who had noble status and control of the juridical machinery (Wallerstein, 1976: 17, [italics added]). The form and content of judicial procedures were based primarily on land tenure and the need to define the subject status of bar- ons and knights in relation to the sovereign. The development of reasonably explicit rules evolved into custom-bound definitions of obligation, inheritance and lineage, rights, and other tasks and responsibilities, and these formed the bulk of civil law. There was emerging in Anglo-Saxon law a clear distinction between public and private offense, although there was no perceptible difference of authorities or procedures in civil and criminal matters before the Normans; graver public offenses, however, were reserved for the King's courts (Pollack and Maitland, 1968: 38). Customs varied dramatically between provinces, shires, and estates, and the practice of law was, as a rule, not the affair of the king. Prior to the eleventh century, criminal offenses, both public and private, were primarily a local matter, and courts were open-air meetings of freemen who were bound to attend them, and there were a number of private, ecclesiastical, local, and sovereign courts in existence to hear cases. These &*(1:-1).[4]&*(0:&*len.) and personal testimony of participants, and the final judgment was given by their acclamation. For this they received compensation in the form of fines and fees. There were no professional judges, lawyers, clerks or other administra- tors, and no records were kept (Pollack, 1968: 89-90). The only "learned men" were the clergy, and this further contrib- uted to ecclesiastical power, since there were at this time no separate ecclesiastical courts in England. The primary royal body, which also heard some of the more serious offenses, was the witenagemot[5], composed of a body of nobles assembled by the king, and invested with limited decision-making duties. The wi- tangemot, however, had little power, and the king was bound to the decisions primarily to the extent of his personal control over it. It would thus be a mistake to see the origins of the state as arising from this body, as it served primarily as a leg- itimizing mechanism for the royal position, possessing modest ad- ministrative tasks rather than existing as a coherent body of law or policy makers. As Oleson (1955: 109) suggests, the witan probably did not function as a high court of justice, and even such sentences as it levied were pronounced in accord with the monarch's wishes. The king's witan, however, did provide a "su- perior authority in reserve" for those desiring a primitive form of appeal. When modern scholars suggest that the drafters of the Magna Carta tended to romanticize the features of Edward's reign, they mean, in part, that the principle of an effective and influ- ential body of royal advisors is exaggerated by subsequent gener- ations who tended to ignore the limitations of its practice. In this period, law and Church were intertwined. By Aethelred's time (979-1016), the bishops were at least as powerful as the king in political and judicial affairs, and the laws of Aethelred have been described as "mere sermons preached to a disobedient folk" (Maitland, 1968: 29). Jurisdiction often overlapped or conflicted, and tensions occurred over who possessed the right to hear particular cases. In serious offenses, courts often became an arena for working out broader territorial and other political disputes at least as much as they were forums of justice. In this period of English law, the state was rarely involved in bringing charges against an individual, and thus there was no need to limit its legal power, since it had none. Saxon kings were elected from among the high nobles and were not yet the cen- ter of justice, which was dispensed on the principle of blood feud. Private wrongs were considered a tort rather than criminal offense, and the existing law specified explicit compensation to be paid to victims or their families if a blood feud was to be avoided. This was later mediated by intervention or negotiation of the clan patriarch who became the de facto magistrate to whom jurisdiction of protection and justice fell (Sharpe, 1976: 2-4). What we have come to know as "criminal procedures," those more or less formal rules applied to assure offenders minimal standards of fairness when called to justice, emerged with the King's peace[6]. The "king's peace" concept was borrowed from the con- tinent, and dated from Anglo-Saxon England, and refers to general guidelines established by the king for mediating disputes as a means of limiting blood feuds, avoiding anarchy, and generally attempting to minimize rebellions created by personal or tribal conflict. In civil law and in personal offenses, grievances were brought by individuals against other individuals, and redress was contingent upon its willingness or ability of the aggrieved party to com- plain and pursue a grievance. The king was, in practice, more the "ultimate temporal avenger of justice" than dispenser of jus- tice, and judgments in court were dependent largely on correct pleadings customarily based on oath[7] On the eve of the Norman invasion, the Old English Kingdom has been described as not much more than a . . .federation of tribal commonwealths for the purpose of mutual defence; the importance of co-operat- ing even for this purpose had been seldom realised ex- cept in the last extremity of danger. Provincial jeal- ousies and the feuds of noble houses had often spoiled the fairest and most needful plans for common action; and unity was preserved much more by the force of sen- timent than from a conviction of expediency (Davis, 1957: 4). Kings still customarily distributed to other nobles the jurisdic- tion to hold courts, which meant that the judiciary remained in private hands. If King John was the unwilling thirteenth century natural father of the Magna Carta, then surely Edward the Confessor (1042-1066) should be considered the willing foster father in the eleventh century. The direct substantive antecedents of our own system, that part of which derives from English jurisprudence, arguably took shape prior to the Magna Carta in the reign of Edward. The seeds of judicial review, legal protection, and the supremacy of law over the power of the sovereign were sown, but had not sprouted, during this period. The laws established by Edward the Confessor were actually begun by his grandfather, King Edgar, and served, as judged by the standards of the time, as a model for the definition and distribution of justice. As Sir Matthew Hale (1971: 56) has argued, they were the standing laws of the land, and were held in the same esteem as the Magna Carta became for later generations of British subjects. To summarize, prior to the Norman conquest, the legal system was primitive, and governed relations among equals in status and wealth. The economic bases of the this system assumed the exis- tence of sufficient land to accommodate an increasing population without lowering their standard of living. Lords treated vil- leins as subordinates owing allegiance and resources, and both lords and villeins treated serfs as a commodity, useful primarily for their labor power and what it could produce in the fields or cottage industry. Lords held the legal power over those under them, and manor disputes were rarely referred to the king. Two social features of this period promoted a form of cohesion that contributed to a relatively low crime rate, and thus there was no dramatic need for development or refinement of criminal proce- dures. First was the well-balanced system of social dependence, and second was a universalistic religious ideology that supported the norms and forms of social control to which this system corre- sponded. This gave rise to two forms of law. The first, between lords and serfs, was regional, highly variable, and dealt prima- rily with criminal offenses; the second was between feudal lords, and between lords and the sovereign, was civil in nature. As a consequence, we must recognize the explicit distinction between civil and criminal procedures and who benefited from the growth of law during this period. At the risk of some oversimplifica- tion, we might view criminal law as developing over the next few centuries ancillary to civil law. At the end of Edward's reign, England remained primitive even by European standards of the day. There was little foreign trade, little internal traffic, and a lack of large-scale industry on which commercial interests could develop (Pollack, 1979: 88). The laws of the land primarily served to establish the security of the king and the feudal structure of land tenure, and such rights as were protected were limited to the nobility. The rights of the rest of the population were bound in custom and guaranteed only so far as manor lords were willing to recognize them or insofar as commoners could coerce, through persuasion or threat of violence, adherence. THE NORMAN INVASION, 1066 While it may be unfair to describe the Norman conquest as "the outcome of a struggle, short and spasmodic in its character, be- tween a handful of adventurers and a decadent nation laying on the outer fringe of European politics" (Davis, 1957: 1), there was nonetheless no dramatic break in continuity or custom despite administrative changes. This is largely because the French Prince William came not as a conquistador, but as a legitimate rival claimant to the crown; his victories, therefore, were not so much the conquest of a kingdom by a foreigner as a victory over other pretenders, primarily Edgar Aetheling, favored by the nobility, and Harold, an English rival, who eventually relin- quished his claim to William following his defeat at the Battle of Hastings in 1066[8]. When William the Conquerer (1066-87) finally established Norman domination in England, he found a decentralized system in which justice was still dispensed locally at the discretion of individ- ual noblemen. William, like subsequent Norman kings, enacted few laws, and despite importing some Norman customs, he brought no significant body of law with him[9]. There were no written codes and Norman law did not exist in a transplantable shape. Indeed, one advantage English law had over that of the Normans was that at least some English law was written. Further, Pollack (1979) and Maitland (1968: 74) have suggested that the procedures of the two cultures were not dissimilar. The age of superstition and appeal to divine intervention had passed, and both cultures shared the oath system. Both cultures retained strong Church ties, and in both systems the schisms between Church and state created occasional conflict. In fact, one of William's first acts was to define the relationship of his new kingdom to Rome. He opted for the Frankish system and retained strong, although often acrimonious, bonds. The Norman administration left un- touched the essential feudal agricultural economy, and encouraged the development of inchoate rights while taking away some of the exceptional character of those already established (Davis, 1957: 38). It is this body of law, in fact, which the barons sought to revive 150 years later at Runnymede. There were, however, some consequences of the Norman invasion for the development of English law. In the Norman system, justice flowed from the king, and to implement this, William introduced the King's Council, which eventually replaced the former local- ized court system (Duker, 1980: 14). The Normans also brought the intellectual, administrative and cultural traditions that were to influence English law and its administration for the next several centuries. At this time, the king's legislation was closely connected both to the political and doctrinal interests of Papal authority; William weakened ecclesiastical judicial pow- er by demanding recognition of the King's authority over the Church's, and he confirmed as part of the concessions for his ascension the laws of William the Confessor; these laws became known as the Laws of King William (Hale, 1971: 69). We can see in William's reign several characteristics of state centralization as it shifted to the authority of the king and his courts. First, judicial authority was no longer farmed out, but became an increasing responsibility of the crown. Second, the king began to establish not only formal statutes, but also infor- mal strategies and procedures for dispute resolution that would shape judicial procedure and especially jurisdiction. Finally, the judiciary was beginning to develop as a distinct area of ad- ministration through the establishment of special courts, specif- ic administrators reflecting a changing division of judicial la- bor, expansion of the concept of the king's peace, and attempts--although not completely successful--to promote regional uniformity. LAW AND SOCIETY AFTER WILLIAM THE CONQUERER William's successors were able to maintain and extend the hegemo- ny of an increasingly central system. When William II (William Rufus, 1087-1100) succeeded his father, the rights of the common- ers, never numerous, were in decline. Prior to the Normans, vil- leins (serfs) had under Old English common law modest protections against legal abuses by the lord of the manor. Among these rights included intervention of shire courts to protect commoners from eviction or the arbitrary increase of traditional feudal services. But by the end of the eleventh century, the "new jur- isprudence" of the Normans recognized no limit to the demands which a lord might make upon the time and labor of the villeins, and lords further assumed possession of all the villein held. Although judicial fiefdoms were no longer given to the nobility, lords retained considerable power, even though limited to their domains. In fact, the traditional manor courts, which had exist- ed prior to the Normans, seem to have increased the power of the manor lord while decreasing the rights of the commoner. The lords' responsibility for order among his tenants invested him with a quasi-magisterial authority, a responsibility which did not diminish under the Norman kings. What had previously been granted as a privilege had assumed the status of a right. Wil- liam II did not resolve, nor did he create possible means for ameliorating, the tensions that existed between or within region- al and baronial power and the king. As a consequence, the struc- tural tensions continued to mount as increasing pressure from those competing for power challenged the existing arrangements on which political power was based. He did, however, contribute one important but short-lived modification in criminal proceedings. He introduced the murder fine, or murdrum, which was intended to protect the lives of Normans settling in England who were fre- quently attacked by natives (Poole, 1964: 393). The theory guiding this fine assumed that, unless proven otherwise, if a murder victim was a Norman, a fine was levied by the king against the hundred rather than the offender. This policy reveals, al- beit with some qualification, the idea of public, rather than private, responsibility of and prosecution for what we now call "street crime." The intent was to pressure localities to assume responsibility both for protecting the local population, and for indicting and punishing offenders. This practice is similar to tribal societies in which the group as a whole reacts to preserve order. English society was changing, however, and William's pol- icy did not long-survive. William also abolished capital punish- ment, preferring instead mutilation, but this was reversed under Henry I. Legal change occurs when social formations generate structurally insolvable problems. Such problems become "fundamental" when "individuals or groups repeatedly confront on another with claims and intentions that are, in the long run, incompatible" (Haber- mas, 1975: 27). We call this a structural contradiction. There existed such a contradiction between the emerging centralization of royal control on one hand and the increased power of manor lords over local affairs on the other. Although this system tem- porarily strengthened and stabilized the structure of the crown and judicial powers, it also made it more brittle. The increas- ing complexity of society and law made it impossible to effec- tively deal with new problems arising on the local level, and the existing system was not able to adequately deal with problems of order, let alone new definitions of problems that were emerging. Scholars agree that William II's reign was one of unstable con- tradictory equilibrium and despotism, ruled by a functional il- literate with few administrative skills and even fewer fiscal, diplomatic, or judicial interests[10]. His contributions were few, although he did preserve the administrative structure of his father, and the superstructure of English society remained in a holding pattern at the end of the eleventh century. It has been said that the twelfth century is the "most legal" of all centuries in the Middle Ages, because of the revival of the influence of continental law and the "rediscovery" of the writ- ings of Aristotle, Justinian, and other classics. It does not follow, however, that this legality created a law-abiding socie- ty. The problem of pervasive lawlessness, which existed into the sixteenth century, occurred, in part, because the feudal system required able-bodied males to possess weapons and be reasonably trained in their use. The continual military adventures of the Middle Ages also contributed to a mood of violence, and the re- sult was similar to a problem faced by contemporary society, namely, the arming not only of those necessary to preserve social order, but of those with more predatory interests as well. This facilitated brigandry, violent quarrels, and related offenses, and in general contributed to disruption of law and order. On the other hand, if there was a shortage of justice in the waning years of the eleventh century, there was no dearth of courts: There were the courts of the vill and the manor, hun- dred courts and shire courts, borough courts, honorial courts and the ecclesiastical courts of archbishops and bishops, and the newer courts of archdeacons, and, of course, there was the court of the lord king. In gen- eral terms it is fairly easy to distinguish the compe- tence of each. The humble court of the vill enforced the village by-laws. The manor court was the land- lord's private estate court, hearing cases which arose out of the unfree tenures of his peasantry. The hun- dred court dealt with the petty crimes of lowly men in the neighborhood of a few vills. The shire court, in its judicial aspects, was largely concerned with more serious crimes: felonies, accusations against freemen, tort and pleas of debts. The borough court performed similar functions to the shire court within the bounds of the township and according to the terms of its char- ter of incorporation. Pleas of land, however, and all that arose out of landholding, such as inheritance, down, and a vassal's obligations to his lord, were the peculiar province of the honorial court, the court which a lord summoned for the free tenants of his fief. The ecclesiastical courts, in the words of an edict of William I, were the proper tribunals for "causes which concern the cure of souls"--a sweeping phrase, for by the notions of the time it covered matrimonial and testamentary causes, promises made on oath, besides the discipline of the clergy and correction of sinners. The king's court--a court which met whenever and wher- ever the king chose to convene it--was the greatest ho- norial court in the land, for it was there that the te- nants-in-chief brought their pleas; but it was also the supreme court for the enforcement of all the king's rights and the final court of appeal from lesser juris- dictions (Warren, 1973: 317-18). When Henry I (1100-1135) replaced his brother, he inherited a chaotic kingdom fraught with baronial opposition, and he lacked an effective administrative means other than crude force to re- duce conflict. Following his brother's policies, he attempted to return Normandy to his control, but unlike his brother, who had alienated a large segment of the nobility with demands to finance his military projects, Henry restructured his administration to facilitate revenue collection and policy enforcement. He reorg- between feudal and later councils[11]. Henry also restored the free election of bishops and abbots, and most important, explic- itly reaffirmed the laws of his father, and by extension, Edward the Confessor. English law at this time continued to vary from region to region, and perhaps the most notable of Henry's contri- bution to English law, as well as to the centralization and homo- geneity of the court system, was the establishment of one system of law limited largely to more serious felonies and royal edicts for all regions. The monarchy was strengthened at the expense of feudal power, especially by the introduction within the King's Council of a class of administrators dependent upon the king and by the organization of the Exchequer whose travelling officers heard judicial pleas in the course of their financial duties (Perry and Cooper, 1959). Henry's law has been described as a fusion of Old English law, feudal custom borrowed from the Norman courts, and principles from civil law (Davis, 1957: 136). But he was more pragmatic, and although his laws tolerated some traditional feudal remnants (e.g., wergeld, ordeal), the procedures of the Old English system were gradually replaced by enlightened procedures, but these were often accompanied by more drastic punishment. It has been said that, like Scott's fabled Robin Hood, Henry, despite his extrava- gance, robbed from the rich and gave to the poor (Harvey, 1963: 103). Whether true or not, Henry's fiscal policies were opposed by the nobles, who preferred to pay the king little and extract as much as they could from the peasants (Harvey, 1963: 103). While the rest of Europe was fighting the Mongols, Henry was at- tempting to placate his barons, regain French lands, and unify his administration. It is upon this legacy that the Plantagenet kings built the legal structure that has also provided the roots of our own. THE EARLY PLANTAGENETS Despite the advances of Henry I, it was left to Henry II (1154-1198), following the inept and inconsequential reign of Stephen (1135-1154), to firmly establish a consistently central- ized court system. If the Magna Carta possesses symbolic signif- icance as the legal foundation of modern liberty, then the admin- istrative reforms of Henry II must count as the symbolic beginnings of the judicial and political system on which such liberties could be based. It especially provided fruitful ground for a specifically English form of law to blossom, and softened the ground for the establishment of the Magna Carta several dec- ades later. Stephen had left the kingdom in a state of virtual anarchy, and many of the legal gains were threatened; he had also discouraged the study of common law. One of Henry's first tasks was to re- establish the judiciary as a unified, rational, and above all, tractable force by which to preside over his subjects. Almost immediately he began to . . .meet the vast mass of arrears, the questions of jurisdiction and of disputed property, which had ar- isen even as far back as the time of Henry I, and had gone unsettled through the whole reign of Stephen, to the ruin and havoc of the land in question. He exam- ined every charter that came before him, and, if any was imperfect, he was ready to draw one up with his own hand; he watched every difficult point of law, noted every technical detail, and laid down his own position with brief decision. In the uncertain and transitional state of the law the king's personal interference knew scarcely any limits, and Henry used his power freely (Green, 1968: 121). The second Henry's contributions to jurisprudence of the period were three-fold. The first lay in his judicial reforms. He con- solidated the court system, reformed the municipal laws of the kingdom, and established a more orderly form of administration and procedure than had existed before. He created itinerant com- missioners who travelled the realm and heard pleas, and he limit- ed the barons to settling disputes arising only within their boundaries. Although the practice of sending royal justices into shires had existed under the Norman kings, the practice fell into disuse under the anarchic reign of Stephen. Henry not only re-es- tablished the practice; he refined and expanded it as a systemat- ic form of judicial procedure. Further, although the poorest freeholder was protected by the king's court, the poorer classes were generally not freeholders and still subject to the manor lord (Holdsworth, 1956: 29). Thus, Henry's modifications were implemented primarily in the spirit of maintaining central polit- ical control rather than expanding individual liberties. Henry began the long process of controlling both the power and juris- diction of his clergy, although this task was not to be completed until Henry VIII and the Reformation. Under him the Church claimed jurisdiction of all disputes involving church property or religious matters. Such disputes could be, and often were, broadly defined to allow ecclesiastical jurisdiction over cases that were properly beyond its domain[12]. During this period, the justices were educated and drawn primarily from the clergy. The Church's sophistication in law reflected the "rediscovery" of Roman law, which, in the twelfth century, spread rapidly. Al- though authors write as if Roman law was "lost," it had in fact survived in portions of southern Italy, where it was practiced in what Maitland (1913: 11) has described as a "barbarized and vul- garized form." This sophistication also derived from the underly- ing tradition of training in logic of clerics. Henry's second, and perhaps most significant contribution, lay in his administrative leadership. His administrative acts included separating the Curia Regis into administrative and judicial bod- ies and extending the system of itinerant justices. Under this new system, the Curia Regis became the recognized court of appeal for the entire kingdom, and the work expanded so rapidly that both the personnel and administrative apparatus increased dramat- ically[13]. Under Henry, the Exchequer and the Curia Regis had control of all financial and judicial business of the kingdom. In addition, despite Henry's attempts to regain French lands, his fiscal administration was relatively responsible, giving nobles little cause for revolt. He established relative peace among the bickering nobles and was reasonably successful in limiting eccle- siastical power and external Papal control. Henry also reorgan- ized a standing army and thus decreased (but did not eliminate) his military dependence on the barons, established an orderly method of taxation, and for the first time defined the king's rights in the forests[14]. One continuing problem was the sheriffs, who maintained consider- able independence from the Crown. The position of sheriff, al- though not as fully developed as it would become under Edward III, was even at this time the primary Crown representative in local government. Sheriffs emerged shortly after the Norman con- quest and combined the Anglo-Saxon sheriff with the Norman vi- comte, responsible for fiscal, judicial, administrative and mili- tary organization of the shire (Poole, 1964: 387). They were originally powerful local barons with a vested interest in local affairs, and although the position was normally unpaid, consider- able revenues were to be obtained through both legitimate and il- legitimate performance of duties. Henry began using professional administrators rather than influential magnates as his agents in local government, leading to near-total reorganization of this position. This led to his Inquest of Sheriffs, which resulted in dismissal of most incumbents. Designed as a fiscal reform, it further centralized judicial power in the hands of the Crown. Henry expanded the duties of the sheriffs, which included collec- tion of royal revenues and service and conducting related fiscal administration. He also transformed their purely judicial char- acter, and made them responsible for handling writs, summoning juries, and guarding prisoners (Barlow, 1972: 311). Other legal reforms included drafting new and elaborate rules for royal justices who sat on the Curia Regis[15]. Henry also creat- ed new legal remedies for public and private disputes, and ex- panded the power of his own courts, which, even when rocked by power struggles of later generations, continued to develop. He is also credited, although perhaps with some exaggeration, with establishing the jury system for settling civil disputes. Trial by juries had been used in Athens nearly two millenniums earlier, but the modern form is usually attributed to Henry II. As Terry and Hartigan (1984) have observed, there were important differ- ences between the two, making the Athenian system a distant rela- tive at best rather than a close cousin[16]. At the start of Henry's reign, offenders could be brought to trial in two ways[17]. The first was on appeal, which had a different conno- tation than we know today. In the twelfth century, appeal re- ferred to the process by which a complainant brought the charge to the manor lord or other appropriate local official, and then had to prove the accusation through combat. Evidence suggests that this crude form of trial was not often brought to its ulti- mate brutal conclusion, and it remained an ineffective method of resolving disputes. The second method of bringing a criminal to justice was through public indictment, which was at this time becoming increasingly common. The local community, usually through the hundred, as- sumed responsibility for identifying a crime and, if necessary, prosecuting it. The jury was the body that sought out crime, and it proceeded by customs in existence prior to the Normans but never formally administered until Henry. The jury was essential- ly an information-gathering body, although it did possess some sentencing power. Because the method both of ordeal and combat were discredited, ineffective, or dying out, the jury increasing- ly became significant as the preferred means of processing crimi- nal offenses, and by the early thirteenth century offenders could, for a small sum, have their cases heard by a jury. Changes in law did not occur so much through formal enactments, but through informal verbal instructions given by the king to his ministers or judges, or through changing discretion employed by inferior courts. Henry discovered the difficulties that could be encountered when attempting to implement statutory regulation of those practices that were based on customs or norms, especially when challenging the power of the clergy. The church's preroga- tive was perceived as an encroachment by ecclesiastical courts upon civil jurisdiction, and Henry was alarmed by complaints of scandal and abuses by ecclesiastical tribunals. The Church re- tained courts over not only the entire clerical order, but claimed the right as well to enforce all "matters spiritual," which included cases of oaths, promises, anything to which a man's faith was pledged, to decide the property of intestates, to pronounce in every case of inheritance whether the heir was le- gitimate, and to declare law as to wills and marriages (Green, 1968: 127). In a system still based on land tenure and power by birth right, this provided clergy with considerable power. To combat the pow- er of the clergy, Henry appointed Thomas Becket as archbishop in- tending to create a church more amenable to his will. He also enacted several Assizes[18], the most famous of which is probably the Assize of Clarendon[19]. Henry's final contribution, which may be due in part to histori- cal circumstance, but also certainly due to his judicial reorgan- ization, lay in the creation of common law. Although judges had been guided by precedent and custom prior to Henry, it was large- ly through his reorganization of the judicial process that common law became relatively systematic and recognized as binding. His judges began keeping rolls of their decisions, and lawyers stud- ied these cases. Judicial precedents were established as formal guides for future decisions, and procedures were established for common pleas. The rule of primogeniture (inheritance by the eld- est male son), as Barlow (1972: 318) has observed, became fixed by this time, thus preventing the creation of a caste nobility and pushing the younger sons into the professions, commerce, or industry. By the end of the Henry's reign, the transformation of English law was well underway, shifting from local to central control. Manor courts rarely began, tried, or concluded actions concerning a freehold. The court system had become more specialized and sys- tematic, and the doctrine of common law and stare decisis now, in principle at least, governed procedures. Public prosecutions were becoming more frequent, and the concept of appeal was firmly established at this time, although its meaning was much different than it was to later become[20]. Despite reforms, the law at the time of Henry II was no longer adequate for a society in which the former feudal system was be- ginning to feel the strains of a changing world economic order in which expanding bureaucratic administration, increasingly expen- sive means of waging war, and a slowly, but steadily increasing need for free labor began to shift economic and class power. Nor were the changes in the theory and administration of civil law matched in criminal law. Although the aspects of general crimi- nal procedure are murky during this period (Warren, 1973: 320), it seems that a number of feudal customs remained. Oath and or- deal remained the primary methods of proof[21] in temporal af- fairs, and trial by combat was seldom used in Henry's time. There was still little examination of evidence, and there was no questioning of witnesses. Nonetheless, the rule of law and ad- herence to established universalistic procedures had taken root and began to replace particularistic forms of judgment, and this would soon affect criminal procedures as well. On balance, Henry's reforms, while perhaps not dramatic by con- temporary measure, significantly undermined the existing feudal arrangements which the baronial hierarchy had been accustomed. The outcome of his labor created the foundation of a strong, cen- tralized state. Although many of the consequences would not be evident for several centuries, the law, perhaps more than any other single institution, was being shaped to mediate social change. The structure of an embryonic judicial apparatus was emerging, and it would be used by future generations as a weapon to promote, secure, create, or regain interests that were per- ceived to be threatened. Henry's fiscal and judicial concerns were not shared by the two sons who succeeded him, and this ultimately led to conflict with the nobles and the signing of the Magna Carta. By the reign of Richard (1189-99), proprietary ideas of landholding and ownership were changing, as were the procedures which governed such dis- putes. The king was acquiring the power to decide such differ- ences, and this transferred some legal jurisdiction from regional custom and Church prerogative into the hands of the Crown (Mil- som, 1972). But this transfer was not painless, and it was left to his son John, rather than Richard, to resolve the ensuing con- flicts between church and especially baronial opposition. Richard's interests lay more in military adventure than in admin- istration, and neither politics nor fiscal management distracted him from waging expensive campaigns abroad. His exploits, costly and unpopular, stretched both the ability and willingness of the knights to pay. After the Christian defeat by Saladin (Battle of Hatton, 1187), Richard's goal was to reconquer Jerusalem. This allowed his brother John (1199-1216) the opportunity to build a competing power base in his absence. Following Richard's death in a petty quarrel in France, John was able to resume his goal of reconquering lost territory. John had lost his Norman kingdoms, and in attempting to retrieve them he burdened his nobles with fiscal obligations which they refused to bear. The friction this caused resulted in the signing of the Magna Carta at Runnymede (1215). 3. THE MAGNA CARTA, 1215 Although the view that our own legal system derives largely from the Magna Carta is somewhat mythical, the Magna Carta nonetheless provides a convenient symbolic event. Many scholars trace our legal roots back to the Magna Carta. Although the principles con- tained in the document were not new, they were, for the first time, written down, and symbolized a dramatic transformation in the relationship between law, the state, and society. Like many legal changes, the Magna Carta was the consequence of political and economic crises. Although some (e.g., Painter, 1964: 93) have called the reign of John one of creative experiments, this glosses over his abuses, misjudgments, and misadministration, primarily in levying taxes for unpopular military conflicts and in abusing his power of ar- rest to encourage revenue collection. These took the pattern of increasing customary feudal obligations while decreasing estab- lished feudal rights and protections (Perry and Cooper, 1959: 2). In 1213, when John attempted to revive his war with the King of France, the barons refused to participate, and John attempted to coerce their cooperation. The nobility were now well organized, and in alliance with the London merchants, renounced their alle- giance to John and forced him to meet their demands. Pope Inno- cent III, technically Lord of all England, declared the Magna Carta void, and he reminded the rebelling barons the Pope re- mained their liege[22]. There is evidence that John himself nev- er intended to honor the Charter (Perry and Cooper, 1959), but crisis was averted when both the Pope and the king died within a few months of each other in 1216. The rebellious nobles, aided by those among them with administra- tive or judicial experience, had spent at least two years prepar- ing their document. The text was influenced by the twelfth cen- tury juridical practices of Henry I and Henry II, and romanticized the notion of the principles of procedure under Ed- ward the Confessor in the eleventh century. Among the key chap- ters were protections against arbitrary taxation, the establish- ment of basic judicial procedures, including trial by jury, protections against arbitrary punishment, and above all, adher- ence to the "Law of the Land" (at that time meaning recognition of Edward the Confessor's laws as embodied especially in the statutes of William I). These basic protections not only consol- idated existing judicial protections, but established basic rights[23] that provided the model for subsequent generations of English. The Magna Carta in fact established no new law. Instead it was a demand for the return not so much of the specific laws enacted by Edward, for his legislation was scant, but of the practice of ad- hering to established law. Through this mechanism of redressing grievances, the Magna Carta limited the monarchy and provided in written form the customs which provided the framework for subse- quent legislative and judicial practice for future centuries. The rights and obligations of the King and nobles and the rela- tionship between the two was to be specified, not based on vague promises and coercive force as John had done. The principles contained in the document limited the king's power to arrest no- bles and impose taxes or other obligations without their consent. It defined rights of inheritance, and similar relations between the power of the crown and interests of the nobility. In this way, a conflict essentially class-based in nature developed into a national issue. The Magna Carta provided not only a system of judicial adminis- tration, but provided as well the legitimacy which the barons needed in their quest for power and which the king, albeit un- willing, could use as a legitimating tool to maintain monarchical control. The significance of the Magna Carta, then, lay not sim- ply in the rights it embodied. If this were its primary contri- bution, it would be modest indeed, for many of the rights either had been claimed before or were explicitly protected by previous statutes. Its primary significance was political. For the first time, the powers of the sovereign were definitively limited and a set of legal principles were given primacy over the authority of an individual sovereign. Ironically, while this provided a use- ful mechanism for containing royal power, it also had the conse- quence of expanding the power of the state by creating the admin- istrative machinery and requisite personnel to implement it. It is this legacy that we forget today, and a legacy which led to further opposition from later generations of English against the power of a centralized authority. Upon John's death, his young son Henry III (1216-72), guided by his advisors, reissued the Magna Carta three times with the con- sent of Pope Innocent's successor Honorious III, each time reaf- firming previous rights and on occasion extending them. By 1254, when the knights were summoned to consider new taxes, the Parlia- mentum (or Parliament) was created, and by 1265 the cities and boroughs secured their right to be represented in this new body[24]. Although the significance of this embryonic form of the future Parliament should not be overstated, it does, at least symbolically, mark a general transition in which at least some fiscal and other inter-class conflicts were moved from the mili- tary into the political sphere, and an explicit, but primitive and episodic, central state mechanism was established to mediate them. Assuming some judicial functions allowed this early Par- liament to hear grievances against peers or between peers and the crown. The Parliament also took a more aggressive role in shap- ing legislation and participating in administration. Because of the increased representation, monitoring, and decision making powers, even if sporadic and often informal in nature, this peri- od of Parliament symbolizes the advances the feudal system was making in its growth toward the modern state. Confronting dis- putes in a sanctioned political arena reflected a new form of conflict resolution in which law became a type of social and ad- ministrative cement. By legislatively defining and reaffirming social practices and establishing procedures by which to imple- ment them, the legal machinery was used to steer English society through its transition from one still largely based on organic solidarity into the modern era. By the mid-thirteenth century, the jury system was commonly used and just as commonly abused. Compurgation (the clearing of of- fenders by oaths) continued in many jurisdictions, and in London the testimony of a corpse was even admitted into court (Poole, 1964: 73). Bribery of, perjury by, and violence against jury members illicitly supplemented licit litigation procedures. Criminal law had slowly begun to move out of the manor courts in- to the jurisdiction of the state, and there had been considerable proliferation of standardized writs available for initiating cas- es in both the king's and county courts (Palmer, 1984: 19). The introduction of a second house in Parliament created a de facto estate system, and if we include the clergy, England at this time was composed of three estates (aristocracy, clergy, Parliament), or formal power sharing bodies, which symbolized, although did not cause, the end of the feudal system of administration. Under Henry III, the unlawful arrest or detention, selling or de- laying of justice, excessive taxation, and Forced "loans" led to baronial resistance and the signing of the Confirmatio Cartarum (1297). This had two principle effects on English liberty (see figure 1). First, it established Parliament as the principle representative of government, and thus protected barons, espe- cially against taxation without consent. Second, it reaffirmed the idea of the existence of a supreme, inviolable Law of the Land and provided the first precepts of judicial review. In this limited form of review, the High Court, as Gray (1871: xxv) ex- plains, functioned in part to interpret legislation (but not de- cisions) in order to check "degenerative propensities" in those laws that deviated from common law tradition or established stat- utes of considerable magnitude (e.g., Magna Carta through Edward I). At the close of Henry III's reign, the King's Court was the most powerful institution in the Kingdom, and, in addition to itinerant justices, it was also composed of highly trained offi- cials who regularly travelled the country. Although the court originally held financial, administrative and judicial duties, under Henry the judicial branch was consolidated into a well-organized and smoothly functioning apparatus, further centralizing law, thus firmly establishing separate state courts for criminal and civil proceedings. Holdsworth (1956: 30) has observed that by the end of Henry's reign, the King's Bench and Common Bench were distinct courts each with its own judges, offi- cers, and records. By the beginning of the fourteenth century, the king's court had become the most important judicial body, and was at this time composed of three branches: The Court of the King's Bench, the Court of Common Pleas, and the Exchequer of Pleas. Palmer (1984: 21) has summarized these courts as follows: The Court of the King's Bench was the highest branch of the king's court. Its jurisdiction was particularly related to major (felonious) and minor breaches of the king's peace and to the supervision of the other branches of the king's court. The Court of Common Pleas was by far the busiest branch of the king's court: it handled a wide range of litigation conncern- ing property, obligations, and wrongs. The Exchequer of Pleas, that branch of the king's court particularly associated with the Exchequer, the accounting agency of the royal government, handled matters pertaining to debts owed to the king and those involving charges against officials, such as the sheriffs, who were ap- pointed in and accountable to the Exchequer. In 1300 the Chancery was still primarily the king's secretarial office and issued the writs that originated suits in the king's court; it was not yet the great Court of Chancery that it would [later] become. The public courts at this time were considered "public" because they were courts to which the individuals in a given territory could resort and were in some way related to the central govern- ment. The county courts, also considered public courts, were presided over by the county sheriff and constituted the primary jurisdictional/governmental units of medieval England. There were forty such county courts by 1300 (Palmer, 1984: 20). The contributions of the thirteenth century to our own legal sys- tem stem from three important characteristics of the period. First, the period was marked by an expanding central government under the king which provided the power to initiate and enforce law. Second, in addition to the growth of state power, there be- gan to emerge a professionalization of the administrative appara- tus to carry out the day-to-day juridical tasks. This included the creation and refinement of special courts specifically de- signed to process specific types of cases, new rules and resourc- es funnelled into this apparatus to maintain and develop it, new forms of coercion, which generally relied on the legitimacy of non-violent compliance, and new forms of punishments for offend- ers. Finally, and perhaps most important, there began to emerge a legal ideology in which a solid foundation of systematic law a partially-autonomous nature in which it not only created legiti- macy for royal edicts, but itself took on legitimacy and placed limits both on the power of the sovereign and on other state of- ficials as well. POST-MAGNA CARTA: THE LATER PLANTAGENETS Using the metaphor of seasons, Harvey (1963: 107) has argued that Plantagenet England can be divided into three distinct periods. The spring was ushered in by Henry II, budded at the death of Henry III and began its summer blossom by the reign of Edward I (1272-1307). In the century between Edward and Richard II, ju- ridical reform and administration advanced, and the state took more control over enacting and administering both civil and crim- inal proceedings. In the autumn of the Plantagenets, from rough- ly 1399-1485, legal advances were not particularly significant and rested on the framework created by the three Edwards and Richard II. By the beginning of the fourteenth century and Edward I, the con- cept of "Law of the Land" became synonymous with "due process" and the Magna Carta was firmly established as the model by which to guide judicial procedures. Edward I (1272-1307) continued the fight begun by Henry II against judicial abuses, which had in- creased under Richard and John. Nonetheless, Edward had forgot- ten the lessons of John's experience, and repeated many of his errors. Pricked by the King's violation of established law, es- pecially his propensity for increasing revenue, barons and clergy united to re-establish their rights through law. Edward realized that a powerful central state was required to as- sure his position and contain his fractious opposition, which by now included not only the nobility but a growing middle class of free landholders and commercial interests. Jenks (1968: 54) has observed that English law had been variously declared by kings, landowners, common folk, judges, merchants and ecclesiastics, and it was Edward's strength that "he brought these various groups together to obtain law infinitely stronger, better, juster, above all, more comprehensive, than the separate laws which preceded it." It is this centralization and containment rather than judi- cial changes which characterize his contributions to legal devel- opment. He created a systematic body of public law regulating commerce, trades, and social life. Edward also excluded lawyers from sitting as county representatives to Parliament, arguing they were unqualified to represent county interests. For these reasons, Edward was considered both a great legislator and an adept administrator. Perhaps more than of his predeces- sors, he attempted to settle and establish distributive justice throughout his kingdom (Maitland, 1913: 19), and he has been called the "English Justinian" (Jenks, 1968: 139) largely on the basis of his juridical administration. His policies facilitated the dissolution of patriarchalism and feudalism and consolidated the administration of law. Drawing from the judge and legal scholar Henry of Bratton (Bracton) a few years earlier, Edward solidified English law into a coherent whole which would grow and develop. McKisack (1959: xvii) has described early fourteenth century Eng- land as a prosperous land with an expanding population and flour- ishing agriculture. Nonetheless, such a picture belies the con- tinuing lawlessness and abuses of royal judicial power. After initial bickering over procedure, Edward II (1308-1327) was coro- nated, but agreed to take a fourfold rather than the customary threefold oath. His promises to maintain peace and do justice corresponded to previous oaths, but the fourth required his prom- ise to "maintain the laws and customs allowed by former kings" which amounted to a general agreement to uphold previously estab- lished English law and custom (McKisack, 1959: 5). This was the result of the noble's memories of previous abuses, and represent- ed a further step in the long road toward further establishing the sanctity and autonomy of law over the sovereign. There was nothing revolutionary in this concession, since the principle had been in existence since King John and especially the legal theories of Bracton. But it did symbolize the slowly growing importance placed on liberties, new definitions of legal rights and the subject status of those who enjoyed them. Shortly after Edward's coronation, the Ordinances (1311) restricting the king's free use of power in performing his duties and defining and imposing obligations on his subjects (primarily the nobility) were passed. The Ordinances required regular sessions of Parlia- ment and allowed the Ordainers the right to interpret and clarify ambiguity in legal decisions based on the Magna Carta. Although many of the changes were implicit custom, and although the Ordi- nances were repealed a decade later, they nonetheless signified the growing power of law as a weapon in political conflict and a means of transforming the structure and social relations between ruler and ruled. Edward II expanded the state as a steering mechanism for stabilizing the economic structure through the en- actment of strict wage and price laws and monitored markets, trades, and professions. Under Edward, there was also increased representation of commoners in Parliament, lending both legitima- cy and strength to central administration, and further politiciz- ing both inter- and intra-class conflict by creating access to state power and decision making for non-aristocratic members of society. The essential judicial, Parliamentary, and council structures were sharply defined, and modern historians tend to see in his administrative reforms the contours of an administra- tive structure that has survived in altered form to the present. Despite the significant contributions of the first two Edwards, the reign of Edward III (1327-1377) is perhaps the best known. This is in part because of his contributions to judicial and po- licing administration, but also because of the longevity of his reign. It was during Edward III's reign that the Hundred Years War began and sporadic plagues occurred (1348-49, 1361-62, 1369, 1375). The war, a century-long series of skirmishes between Eng- land and France, placed a drain on crown revenues and contributed to the continuing rise of Parliament, on which the king depended for resources. The Parliament of April-May 1341 secured a number of concessions from the king. These included protection of the clergy against arbitrary arrest and encroachments on their juris- diction, peer protection against being tried by other than the king except in Parliament and before peers, and a general conces- sion that breaches of the Great Charter be reported in Parliament and redressed by the peers of the land, whatever the status of the offender (McKisick, 1959: 173-74). Parliament also became more representative at this time, including lords, clergy, and representatives from shires, cities, and boroughs. The plague further contributed to the crises of the period. The first plague had perhaps the most immediate impact, since it fell hardest on older and more prominent people (McKisick, 1959: 331). Although the aristocracy seems to have been much less af- fected by the plague than commoners in the next two outbursts, they were not unaffected. This increased the problems of deter- mining land or estate inheritance through the high death rate which on occasion eliminated all natural heirs or left ambiguous the rights of potential heirs. It also disrupted commerce, trav- el and production by decimating the labor force, fostering local isolation in those communities not yet suffering from disease, and in general creating an environment of chaos. Edward also dramatically altered the role of justices of the peace. Prior to Edward, policing of criminal offenses was a com- munity, not a state, endeavor, and juries, townships and villages could be fined if they either did not report malefactors or if they did not meet quotas (Green, 1968: 130). Edward enacted a statute that every shire was to select "good and lawful men" to keep the peace, and a second statue provided for three or four notable citizens to have the power of arrest, receive indictment, and hear and judge various felonies according to the "law and customs of the realm." By 1388, these groups were directed by statute to meet four times a year, and were now called "justices of the peace." Also under Edward III, the inns of the court of London took on the character of a legal university, and although the language was French, the laws studied were explicitly English (Tout, 1905: 426). When Richard II (1377-1399) ascended the throne, he was confront- ed with dramatic social transition created by the plague, and the political apparatus created by his predecessors nearly collapsed. Population growth increased dramatically, cottage industries were increasing in economic importance, and the power of the landed class was beginning to be challenged by mercantilist interests, which would create substantial problems in the next century. A significant phase in the development of legal administration had ended with Edward III, and an hiatus of sorts set in. During his short reign, Richard II was unable to consolidate his government. He died leaving it a battle ground of vested interests. Although his successors were able to establish order and a re-unified kingdom, never again was the crown able to influence law and courts to the extent of the previous Plantagenets. Under the three Henries there was no systematic development in the administration of law, and the reign of Richard III (1483-1485) was too short to leave any lasting accomplishments. The nature of the state, which in England had begun to emerge af- ter the consolidation of political power under William I, and be- come more firmly established under the political and juridical consolidation of Henry II, was continuing its transformation. From a system in which a sovereign claimed direct control over the subjects and established a bureaucratic administration to consolidate power and control, the bureaucracy now emerged as a partially autonomous entity in which its interests coincided and acted in alliance with the sovereign. As religious, social, eco- nomic and demographic changes created new crises and required new forms of resolution not always consistent with the ability of the existing political system to meet them, existing institutions changed, former institutions passed out of existence, and new forms of administration and control emerged to mediate the con- flicting parties and their various interests. By the end of the Plantagenet period in the late 1400s, there were disputes which courts of common law hesitated to hear, according to Wilkinson (1964: 266), for sound legal reasons[25]. The Inns of Court, and thus not surprisingly lawyers, were drawn from the aristocracy, and this influenced to some extent both their judgments and the political use to which they put law in alliance with other members of their class[26]. Along side these structurally-induced changes, there still existed conflicts with- in the various classes for dominance. This effectively split po- litical opposition and thus allowed the king to retain control of the legal apparatus. Wilkinson (1964: 198) has argued that law at this time "spoke with a divided voice." Fifteenth century lawyers rejected the Roman law maxim that "what pleased the king had the force of law," but recognized the crown prerogative and power in judicial matters. If there was strong feeling that judges must abide by the "Law of the Land," there was also a counter-current as well that the king was above the law and explicit crown judgments (when not affect- ing their own courts) were above their jurisdiction. The old es- tate system was breaking down, feudal lords were losing power, and the broadening of English liberty now encompassed the middle classes (Wilkinson, 1964: 204) as the rights of the aristocracy were now shared by a new body of middle class power seekers. Throughout the Middle Ages, judicial administration was part of the stakes in the perpetual battles over royal administration. The feudal aristocracy was in decline, the merchants and large producers ascending, and the struggle for political and economic dominance both between these groups and between them and the state led to repeated clashes over which law became both an in- strument for opposition and a victors' spoil of conquest. When Richard III (1483-1485), the last of the Plantagent Kings, assumed the throne, England was in a state of anarchy. However, the structure of law, was useless in maintaining social order and preventing faction fights. It nonetheless remained intact and in uneasy tension with the king: Certainly the judges had recognized that Parliament made the law, in accordance with which the king should reign, but the king himself could do no wrong which the judges could remedy, and Parliament was still his high court. The great officers of state, the judges, the sheriffs, and the mayors all exercised their authority in the name of the king, and although, during the trou- bles of the Roses, irregularities had crept into the system, the system itself was still intact (Mackie, 1966: 12). The end of the Plantagenets marked the end of a social era, as England moved out of the medieval into the pre-industrial period, taking a major step toward modernization. Although there re- mained lingering traces of the old feudal order, growing national and international economic interdependence had made the social relations on which the self-contained manor system was based in- effective, and they could not compete with the emerging capital economy. Trade, migration, science and technology, specialized division of labor, and a mix of labor, capital and intensive pro- duction made the owning or holding land insufficient for generat- ing wealth and power. Further, it was no longer as easy to mobi- lize and provide for a private army because of the changes that technology had brought to warfare. Fortifications, weapons and training were too expensive for most nobles, thus centralizing legitimate force under the state. England still had a rural economy, but even in the late fifteenth century displaced agri- cultural workers were moving into larger urban areas. This dis- placement was in part responsible for increased crime on the highways and in towns, as the population growth was, in most areas, occurring more rapidly than was the means to assimilate newcomers. The means of sustaining the population, previously done on farms or the manor, was being supplanted by wage labor, which meant that those without jobs had little way to subsist. This was also a period not only of domestic power shifts between estates and new classes, but of international alignments as well. To meet these problems, new laws, especially criminal laws, were passed, designed primarily to protect commerce and property[27]. In short, as English society became more modernized through new forms of commerce, industry and technology, new legal forms emerged to promote and protect these emerging social relations, and this was the problem which taxed the Tudors. 4. THE ENGLISH TRANSITION: 1485 TO 1700 The beginning of the Tudor period, beginning with Henry VII, marked the end of one era of English law and the beginning of an- other. Law, under the Tudors, became more rational, more bureau- cratic, and the concept of rights began to be recognized as a fundamental aspect of society, and extended to broader social groups. But the transformation in law did not occur automatical- ly; it came about because of numerous social conflicts and events that created new problems for which law was seen as a useful rem- edy or weapon. THE TUDOR PERIOD The fifteenth century ended with the War between the Red Rose of Lancashire and the White Rose of York at the Battle of Bristol in 1485. This "War of the Roses" has been described as "the last faction fight between organized gangs of barons for control of the government" (Hill, 1969: 29). While this may be overstated, this dynastic quarrel was, as Fisher (1919: 2) states, sterile of ideas and principles and prolific of sporadic anarchy. When the dust settled, Henry VII regained the Kingdom for a line of Welsh- descendents kinds and queens with his victory over Richard III, transformed political alliances, shifting the balance of class power. While under the Tudors there were no dramatic legal or juridical changes comparable to the Magna Carta, the Tudors' political im- pact on law was profound. Under both Henries, but also under their successors, the Tudors enacted a variety of statutes de- signed to control the movement of displaced rural dwellers, regu- late and protect skilled workers and artisans, and secure smooth production and distribution of goods for the growing merchant class. These statutes favored the gentry at the expense of the aristocracy, and finally completed the erosion of the administra- tive and juridical machinery on which feudal power was based. The increased status of the House of Commons meant that the House of Lords shared Parliamentary power, which increased both the rights and expectations of non-nobility. Litigation, as a means of resolving economic and political conflicts and property rights (although not yet personal harm), increased dramatically. Juries and judges, however, were still not fully autonomous, and could be influenced, bribed, coerced and terrorized, either through pressure brought by the Crown or by other powerful landed or aristocratic groups. It was not until late in the next century that relative indepen- dence was secured. Henry VII extended the mandate of justices of the peace, and they were commanded, under penalty of fine or dis- missal, to take a more aggressive role in combating counterfeit- ing, murder, robbery and other felonies. The Court of Wards, a new court created to exploit the remaining fiscal aspect of feu- dalism, transferred the administration of revenues from the Chan- cery and Exchequer, thus expanding the royal prerogative for rev- enue collection. Nonetheless, there appears to be little evidence that Henry's attempts to curb lawlessness met with con- siderable success, and during this period even the Star Chamber did not take any significant initiative in prosecuting offenders (Chrimes, 1972: 186). During Henry VII's time, there is no evi- dence that the Star Chamber heard felonies, and there is no known instance of state initiation of litigation. The bulk of its cas- es were private suits alleging rioting, and miscellaneous civil suits and municipal and trade disputes constituted a large pro- portion of the remainder (Chrimes, 1972: 148). The Council Learned, on the other hand, served a different function, and its cases dealt with Crown prosecutions and Crown debts. Despite his administration and attempted reforms, Henry VII's primary interest lay in enforcing laws in which the Crown had a direct financial interest. There were neither gains nor losses in the power of Parliament, although the King was still dependent upon it for revenue. Henry's King's Council had further central- ized the state's legal powers by transforming its powers as an advisory council to a formal court of law. Henry VII did not fundamentally change the judicial structure, but he did smoothly manage its administration. He was not considered an excessive law maker, even though his laws have been described as possessing exceptional merit. But in the main, Henry's statutes were not of major importance. When Henry VIII (1509-1547) assumed power, the legal system of England, like the society itself, was in a state of chaotic tran- sition. The judiciary, laws, and procedures, despite the reforms of previous centuries, were entering the modern era as a hodge- podge of traditions, statutes, practices, and often inconsistent statutes. New laws and procedures were enacted, others fell into disuse, and there was little effort to streamline or rationalize the legal system as there had been under the second and third Henries or the three Edwards. Such factors as governmental rep- resentation, criminal and civil procedure, inheritance rights, Crown prerogative, land and property titles, commerce, navigation and shifting social classes placed additional strains on the ex- isting system. This was further complicated by a high crime rate and a plethora of unsettled definitions of rights. This added to the burden of the existing courts and taxed their abilities to arrive at consistent and appropriate resolutions to the qualita- tively new and quantitatively overwhelming number of suits brought before the courts. This realignment of power exacerbated class tensions, which were to erupt in the next century to chal- lenge the monarchy, transferring power from the crown to a fairly independent bureaucratic apparatus. The "Tudor Revolution" in law and government was propelled by rapid social transformations as the country moved from feudalism into a pre-industrial, international economic system, and law was used as one weapon by which the Tudor rulers guided this tran- sition. The first tasks of Henry VIII included conquering the lawlessness of the nation and curbing the power of the Church. In attempting to rationalize the Crown's legal procedures, Henry created a new council and divided it into the Council at Court and the Council in the Star Chamber. The former ultimately be- came the Privy Council, attending to matters of foreign and do- mestic policy, and the latter became the hated administrative and judicial branch that was disbanded in the early seventeenth cen- tury[28]. Yet, despite the emergence of a powerful merchant and nascent in- dustrial class, the mid 1500s were still dominated by great lan- downers, although the peasant revolt of 1549, the last major in- surrection of its kind, challenged their hegemony both in politics and law. The Church remained powerful, but Henry soon moved to reduce their political and economic power by redistri- buting Church land. The most significant act of the period was the Act of Supremacy (1534), and in the seven years in which Hen- ry's Reformation Parliament met, it severed the ties of England to Rome and established royal supremacy over the church. It also dissolved the smaller monasteries, initiated a redistribution of national wealth and implemented a land settlement of church land. It strengthened royal power, and if the king benefited from this centralization, so did his administrators. Prior to the Reforma- tion, the sovereign was dependent on the Pope to control the clergy who wielded political power by means of their position, and economic power through the lands they owned and the consider- able revenues these generated. The Reformation, as Hill (1969: 35) has observed, not only subordinated the national church to the king but it also subordinated parishes to squires. The gen- try replaced monasteries not only as landowners but also as re- cipients of tithes and as patrons of livings. In the reign of Henry VII, Parliament increased in importance. The monasteries were secularized, thus limiting the power of the clergy, and enclosure increased the amount of pasture land, thus contributing to the expansion of the English textile trade. The economic decentralization of feudalism was, by the sixteenth cen- tury, being consolidated by larger oligarchies which controlled, or at least shaped, production and distribution, thus contribut- ing to their growing political influence. The tug-of-war over control of Crown administration that characterized previous cen- turies had given way to the realization that a strong national government, and by implication, a strong national judiciary, was simply good business. The struggle between royal pretenders which had characterized the previous centuries was replaced by - 39 - internal lawlessness and a growing population, a large proportion of which was displaced from agriculture and either moved to urban areas or created havoc in the countryside through brigandry. There were no foreign lands to be militarily reclaimed, but there were new lands to be exploited for economic purposes. militaris- tic adventurism and the feudal laws it required was replaced by economic adventurism and a new legal framework to support it. England had become an equal in the European community, and the state had become, by the time of Henry VIII, a strong, central force both of social control and conflict mediation. During the sixteenth century, Henry and Elizabeth were besieged by demands for legal changes in criminal procedure. In previous centuries, it was the conflicts between the nobility and crown and the crown and church operating within the feudal context of land and fiscal disputes which shaped law. The driving force be- hind legal reform had shifted to groups demanding new definitions within a neo-modernist society in which the state, once having centralized its control over the judicial machinery, was also ex- pected to use that machinery to honor the ideological justifica- tions it used when consolidating its own power. The Reformation Act destroying the power of the church, laws enacted to control crime, civil disputes, disruptive behavior, trade, population movement, as well as the multitude of new taxes to increase rev- enue, was essentially carried out through the legitimacy of law under the guise of representation. Despite Crown willingness to use force to coerce compliance to royal edicts, the Tudor revolution was nonetheless a revolution by statute. This legal revolution, however, carried with it a contradiction in that the new laws not only implied new rights often incompatible with existing ones, but also elevated the role of law as a necessary means of carrying out Crown authority. These legal changes promoted the litigiousness for which the six- teenth century is noted (Hill, 1969: 49), and increased the con- tributions especially of the gentry and merchants to the develop- ment of law. This generated a movement to rationalize, humanize, and extend the law and its procedures. These new laws created new relationships, obligations and crimes, resulting in inconsis- tent procedures incompatible with changing social expectations and needs. Trials, for example, retained part of their medieval informality but were now becoming encumbered by the advance in procedural rules. England was drawing from Renaissance legal thinking in both philosophy and substance, and the system of jus- tice, drawing from its independent roots, took on a character much fairer than in Europe[29]. In the sixteenth century, an appellant could still legally appeal a case through trial by battle, although this was rare. The in- creasing number of statutes also expanded the rights and motiva- tions of private individuals to litigate, rules of evidence were allowing more testimony and written documents into court, and the role of witnesses expanded. All of this required new procedures to accommodate these practices. This led to the elimination many medieval writs, the Crown prerogative, and archaic forms of evi- dence. These were replaced with a more rational, efficient system to meet the increasingly complex litigious needs of a nation on the eve of the industrial revolution. Following the brief and irrelevant reign of Edward VI (1547-1553), the two Tudor Queens did not so much alter the legal system as shape through legislative means the social fabric in which it was practiced. Neither Mary (1553-1558) nor Elizabeth (1558-1603) significantly altered the legal or judicial machin- ery, and in fact maintained considerable continuity from Henry's period. Under Mary, and later Elizabeth, the policies of enclo- sures were reduced, if not abandoned; Mary prevented restoration of monastic lands, and as Hill (1969: 32) has argued, the Commons was able to use social conflicts to challenge crown power and policy. Mary reversed Henry's policy toward Rome by re-estab- lishing the primacy of the Church through revision of his anti- Papal legislation. She did not, however, significantly change other domestic legislation, leaving both policy and machinery relatively intact. Following Mary, Elizabeth's 60 year reign was a period in which the use of law, although not its procedures, became a refined and effective means of consolidating power, regulating social rela- tions, and attempting a planned national economy. Resolving ten- sions from rapid domestic change was compounded with foreign threats, especially from Spain and France. Internally, the oppo- sition between Catholics and Protestant groups threatened to de- velop into a social crisis. Elizabeth created a variety of new administrative positions to expand the machinery of government, and there was some feeling that these positions were too-often falling in the hands of persons of "low birth" (Ashton, 1984: 57). Elizabeth relaxed usury laws which contributed to economic growth, and her Statute of Artificers, ostensibly economic legis- lation, had broader significance: It was no less--and perhaps even more--significant as an instrument of social control, police, and public or- der, a means by which the government, lacking a civil service and a police force, sought to regulate employ- ment and guard against unemployment; 'to help to ad- vance husbandry, to banish idleness (there was no pro- vision for compulsory direction of labour); 'to reform the unadvised rashness and licentious manners of youth; to avoid many untimely and discomendable marriages' (by insisting on a long apprenticeship of seven years); and 'to bring the aged Artificer to a staid state of liv- ing.' The statute was the government's first line of defence against poverty, unemployment and the dangers to public order associated with them (Ashton, 1984: 105-106). Elizabeth also increased the power of justices; they could now arrest suspects, deal with various misdemeanors and try any ind- ictable offense except treason. Elizabeth reversed Mary's stance toward Rome; she continued Hen- ry's opposition to the Church, because of the fear of cleric en- croachment, because of Papal Francophilism, and also because of Papal support of her rival to the crown, Mary Stuart. On the other hand, a complete breach with Rome was considered dangerous because of England's military and economic weaknesses (Black, 1959: 7). Her Act of Supremacy (1559) provided a means of de- stroying Mary's pro-Rome "reactionary" legislation and in essence revived the anti-papal statutes of Henry VIII, which resulted in Crown assumption of all national power over the Church (Black, 1959: 14). This religious revolution was conducted through legislation rath- er than military force, and law became a powerful tool for regu- lating the social development and control of a potential politi- cal threat while simultaneously disrupting the growth of political and religious ideology. There was not, however, an ea- sy solution to the problem of Puritanism, which had evolved into an intellectual, ideological, and political force with its sepa- ratist doctrine of theology. Since this problem could not be re- solved, it was simply managed, largely through suppressive legis- lation, until the smoldering problem erupted in the seventeenth century. By the end of the Tudor period, a number of substantive changes had been made that influenced the future development of judicial administration. First, and perhaps most important, the adminis- tration of law under the Angevins and especially the Tudors had become firmly centralized and judicial power had become, despite the continued existence of inferior courts, located in the au- thority of the Crown. While some remnants of feudal tradition remained, neither the barons nor the manorial system held econom- ic or political significance. Second, the position of law as su- perordinate to the Crown was firmly established. This hardly prevented abuses of power by the Crown, but it nonetheless re- quired that even the most flagrant abuses be done under the color of law. Third, the separation of civil and criminal law was be- coming more pronounced, and many of the fundamental criminal pro- cedures to which we adhere today had begun to emerge both in principle and in practice. The essential procedures were regular use of trial by jury, the procedure of "fairness" in hearing evi- dence, and most important, the writ of habeas corpus, which would later be used by the opponents of the Stuarts as a political weapon in the seventeenth century. Finally, there emerged equity courts which to some degree challenged the jurisdiction of courts of common law. One advantage of common law and the corresponding courts was the protection against the personal whim or abuses of power of individual justices, or against ephemeral fads which changed definitions and sanctions for offenses. On the other hand, because common law gave primacy to precedent and the test of time, it was slow to change. As a consequence, decisions were not always appropriate for the rapidly changing Tudor period. Almost equal in authority to the courts of common law was the court of chancery. This was really an equity court--a court that is, to remedy injustice which might ensue from a strict interpretation of the common law-- but by this time the chancellor, in his judicial capac- ity, was something more than a keeper of the king's conscience. His court dealt with cases which fell out- side the somewhat cumbrous processes of the common law- -for instance, it recognized uses--and, partly because it sat out of term time, it gradually assumed a juris- diction comparable with that of other central courts (Mackie, 1966: 194). It must be emphasized that despite the development in the theory of legal rights during this period, the practice of legal rights was limited to powerful groups: for the common subject, redress of grievances remained limited. This paucity of rights was fur- ther restricted by the numerous laws attempting to control an in- creasing number of dispossessed, landless, unemployed former peasants, as well as the emerging class of workers and small mer- chants. Laws passed by the state to promote economic interests conducive to the growth of industry and commerce compelled semi- skilled laborers to work in their crafts and to work in agricul- ture. By statute, children were expected to follow the occupa- tions of their parents, and limitations of movement were imposed on workers (Hill, 1969: 57). Such laws helped preserve a pool of cheap labor for both agricultural and quasi-industrial districts, which further strengthening the economic position of the gentry at the expense of the landed aristocracy. The increasing impor- tance of money and the corresponding importance of wage labor led to new laws regulating each. This contributed to the ambiguity, confusion and contradictions in the content of law by creating economic conflicts and social discontents that the Stewarts were not adequately able to resolve. In sum, the Tudor contribution lay in the expansion of legal rights to a broader class of subjects. They somewhat unwillingly established Parliamentary representation of groups with often an- tithetical interests to the House of Lords, created a more cen- tralized state without external (Papal) interference in adminis- tration and law, and secured a governmental structure conducive to the emerging economic interests that provided the impetus for the industrial revolution. As Knafla (1977: 7) has observed, this was also a time in which English humanists pressured the nation's institutions to adopt the love and respect for pure learning that existed in the uni- versities, and to modify the form and structure of government and law accordingly. For the first time in English history, knowl- edge had begun to be used as an instrument to guide social and judicial policy, rather than merely being a subservient partner in maintaining existing power and privilege. The sixteenth cen- tury was a period of rapid social and political transformation. Corresponding changes in the sixteenth century were far more dra- matic, both in the extent of change and in the social trauma these changes caused. The Tudor era was marked by the rise of rational agriculture and the expansion of a capitalist structure which destroyed the last remnants of autonomous production and local independence. Enclo- sure laws reduced agriculture, but promoted sheep farming, thus contributing to the quality of wool and boosting the textile in- dustry's expansion into foreign markets. Industries producing consumer goods flourished, as did the industries of fishing, pro- cessed goods (glass, cutlery), food (salt, beer, soap, sugar) and transportation (wagons, cooperage, ships, roads). New laws to protect and promote production, as well as laws to regulate transportation and redefine obligations between industrial par- ticipants flourished. Unlike the present, there were no previous models or historical lessons from which to draw, and one function of Parliament was that of presenting to the crown those problems for which change was required. The redirection of capital from personal consump- tion to investment aided revenue growth even as it required state expenditures. This led to the reform of fiscal administration and the corresponding legal apparatus by which to implement poli- cy. Relationships between employee and employer were continually changing. The stratification that capital, rather than land, created transformed power and interests. As ashton (1984: 34) has suggested, such class stratification became a dominant feature of Tudor society. Unlike previous centuries, when social transfor- mations were slow and replacement of power relations gradual, in sixteenth century England they were rapid. The weakening or elimination of one social group or legal relations often left a vacuum in which there was neither time nor possibility for smooth transition and accommodation. Unlike state policies prior to Henry VIII, which were designed to restrict capitalist relations, the sixteenth century was marked, especially after the 1550s, by attempts to enhance them. Spurred by the integrative force of a national economy, England was becoming more homogeneous in culture, language, customs and law. Theater, literature, and similar factors had the affect of creating a national culture, and this homogeneity, coupled with the need to promote harmonious conditions to facilitate industry, had the affect of beginning a trend toward unification that was to last until the late 1700s. The monarchy was both strengthened and weakened by a centralized state based on an interlocked na- tional and international economy. In this system, state resourc- es were used to facilitate economic growth and protect the privi- leges and rights of a growing proportion of the population, who reaped their benefits. The state was strengthened through the increased fiscal and judicial power it was able to consolidate and wield, through mobilization of a strong army and police sys- tem, and through both the right and power to define and enact the "proper order of things." It was weakened, however, by these same characteristics. The army, although drawing most officers from the ranks of the nobility, was democratized, especially in the lower ranks; the thriving economic conditions, which the crown promoted and protected, expanded the numbers and power of mer- chants and industrialists; the expectations of the population as a whole grew and became political weapons in Parliament's opposi- tion to crown policies; and the unregulated growth of capitalism brought by unemployment, dislocated farmers and workers, and ur- ban overload and thus created ecological, criminal, and distribu- tion problems far beyond the ability of Tudors or early Stuarts to resolve them. Thus the legitimacy of crown power was threat- ened. The law became a tool of oppression used to quell social opposition, and the courts often took on a quasi-control func- tion. Poor laws, work houses, houses of correction, and vagabond laws had quieted the poor but left the underlying problems in- tact. Different social needs bred different ideologies, both political and religious, by which persons attempted to accommodate them- selves to their lot. Class divisions, wider than at any previous time in England, generated discontent and proved fertile ground for seeds of new religion to grow. The growth of printing, revo- lutionized by Johann Gutenberg in the 1520s, contributed to both discontent and the expansion of law. New political ideas stimu- lated by the Renaissance, and promoted the growth of humanism in Europe. These ideas crept into English legal, political and so- cial thought in the seventeenth century. Religious ideas, too, spread rapidly as literature became more available to larger so- cial groups, and contributed as well to a growth in literacy, al- beit still beyond the reach of the bulk of the population[30]. The officer ranks of the military became more open to the non-no- bility, and this contributed to the reduction of its class-based nature and made the military less an instrument used in factional struggles. By the end of the Tudor period, court procedures were relatively fixed. Civil and criminal laws were distinct, as were the court procedures and jurisdictions for hearing relevant cases. Law had taken on a universalistic character previously unknown. The state had begun using laws not only to protect its hegemony, but to re- solve conflict, facilitate commerce and industry, and to settle private disputes in the civil sphere. It was not until the con- tinued expansion of industrialism and the social tensions this generated that the rights of the nobility were extended to all subjects, which has guided the development of our own procedures. At the beginning of the seventeenth century, the combination of class and ideological, especially religious, difference presented the Stuart kings with problems they were never able to resolve. THE STUART PERIOD Although James I (1603-1625) himself made no dramatic changes in the law, this was nonetheless a period of social change and re- pression. The succession from Elizabeth to James I was orderly, but he was being challenged by Protestant forces from one side and demands by economic interests for more power sharing from an- other. Social cleavages were beginning to again disrupt the cen- tral state, and religion and class pressures were the driving forces. England had changed, the balance of power shifted, and the system of common law was in jeopardy. The growing organization and jurisdiction of the court of Star Chamber, the creation of the various subordi- nate Councils throughout the country, the rapid devel- opment of the court of Chancery and the Court of Re- quests, and the growth of the jurisdiction of the court of Admiralty threatened the supremacy of the common law system. All these courts acted upon principles and by means of a procedure unknown to common law (Holdsworth, 1956: 508). These problems were later complicated by Charles I's need for revenue to support military ventures and to protect colonial ex- pansion abroad. Further, the abuses of the Star Chamber mobi- lized popular opinion as well as powerful interest groups against it, and conflicts arose over attempts to abolish it. Its viola- tion of the principles of law, its apparent abuse of fundamental tenets laid out in the Magna Carta, the perceived excessive pen- alties it imposed, and its use as a means of exerting Crown pre- rogative contributed to unified opposition especially among groups with newly-created economic, political and ideological in- terests. Law became one focal point in social struggle. Seven- teenth century England was stepping into the industrial era, and the legal changes, like those in the political, economic and so- cial spheres, were often dramatic, sometimes traumatic. The 1600s were marked by changes in the substance of criminal and civil judicial procedure impelled by the last clash between the dying landed aristocracy and the emergent gentry and economic or- der. The clashes contributed to the movement for legal reform, especially in the decade prior to the regicide of Charles I (Veall, 1970). Conflicts over taxation, liberties of subjects, religion, land and trade, authority and property again strained the legal machinery to find rational, consistent resolutions to these new problems (Briggs, 1983: 134). The printing press be- came a formidable weapon in political debate, and law became a means for both protecting and suppressing freedom of speech. The middle of the sixteenth century was characterized by the improve- ment of roads, the rise of urban areas, especially London, the rise of printing, the growth of international law, the introduc- tion of a planned economy, and the final disappearance of feudal remnants. The King's authority was increasingly used to enforce policies by unpopular and arbitrary methods (Briggs, 1983: 140), and this contributed to a loss of legitimacy of Crown authority and in the courts. The powers of arrest and seizure were used by the Crown to suppress dissent, discontent, and the new "radical- ism" in politics and religion. This led to resistance by the king's opponents, and prompted strenthening of habeas corpus law. James had abused the law by abolishing judges who refused to de- cide cases to the king's liking and circumventing statutes to control his opposition, a practice continued by Charles. The Two Charles. Charles I (1625-1649) found in law a convenient weapon for har- assing or disposing of those who would challenge its power. Dom- inant legal issues of the period include the power of arrest and freedom of speech. The latter was particularly important, since many political issues took religious form. In a period of relig- ious revival and conflict, the growth of Protestantism, dissent in and challenges to the policies of the established church and state edicts that functioned to thwart such growth, the freedom to publicly express these ideas became a major public and ulti- mately legal issue. Like many of his predecessors, when pressed for increased rev- enues, Charles attempted to raise them through coercion in the form of forced loans. There occurred a debate over the extent of the king's power and whether it exceeded the common law adjudica- tory process. The result was the Petition of Right (1628) which declared that the crown could raise money neither through forced loans nor without the explicit consent of Parliament. It also contained protections against billeting of troops, martial law, and above all, arbitrary imprisonment, and these ultimately found their way into the Bill of Rights of the U.S. Constitution. bil- leting of troops, martial law, and above all, arbitrary imprison- ment. Although Charles violated the Bill's provisions within a year, it nonetheless provided both legal power and precedent for his opposition and contributed to the list of crimes with which he was ultimately charged and executed two decades later. The Petition of Right thus stands as the first of a series of enactments in the seventeenth century by which the writ of habeas corpus was made an effective mechanism for the protection of the right of personal liberty (Perry and Cooper, 1959: 71). Opposition to this oppression led to the Habeas Corpus Act (1640) which abolished the Star Chamber and all the conciliar courts, and provided that anyone imprisoned by the King or his council be brought to trial without delay and cause of imprisonment shown. Abolishing the Star Chamber intended to put writ of habeas corpus on firmer basis, but effective means for enforcement was not ful- ly established until the subsequent Habeas Corpus Act (1679). These legal protections had little immediate impact on other courts. But they did signify an explicit change in the expansion of the writ and provided a model on which subsequent legislation for protecting liberties would be based. The Stuart reign was interrupted by the regicide of Charles at the hands of Puritan opposition who saw the King's continued abuses as violating both the laws of Enlgand and the laws of God. To justify the execution of the monarch, the only such regicide in English history, his opponents appealed to law, citing numer- ous violations of both common and statutory law. This was a form of popular uprising, led primarily by Puritan dissenters in alli- ance with non-gentry freeholders, commercial and other interests. It was not strictly a religious upheaval. Rather, as in twenti- eth century Ireland, class divisions often coincided with relig- ious ideology, conflating the two. James had held that his au- thority derived directly from God and that he was supreme lawgiver. Parliament, he contended, was merely an advisory body (Ashley, 1966: 59). This posture was continued by Charles II, and the policies he enacted alienated especially those of the lower classes and those who had been excluded from power by the Royalist monopoly. As a consequence, opposition to the laws that protected the power and property arrangements of one group tended to be linked especially to Puritanism, and the king did not hesi- tate to use law to challenge this opposition. Cromwell and the Commonwealth. Following the trial of Charles II and the civil war, Oliver Crom- well intended to establish a Commonwealth derived from natural law based--in theory at least--on the "will of the people" rather than royal authority. Cromwell, by most accounts, was committed to liberty of conscience and the view that the laws of the crown were not above the laws of God. The theory of natural law shaped the legal philosophy of the Commonwealth and provided the justi- fication for many of the proposed reforms. It is from this be- lief in liberty of conscience that many of the basic rights later embodied in this English Bill of Rights, the charters of the American colonies, and the U.S. Bill of Rights were derived, es- pecially the freedoms of thought, speech, press and trade. This Free State abolished the House of Lords and the office of king as "unnecessary, burdensome, and dangerous to the liberty, safety and public interests of the people of this nation" (Buchan, 1937: 324). One of the first tasks of the leaders of the new Common- wealth following the execution of Charles I was the reformation of law. While the Rump Parliament that sat following the execu- tion of Charles had delayed reform, Cromwell's new assembly at- tempted to codify and reform the system: pickpockets and horse thieves were not to be executed for their first offense, that women were not to be burnt alive, that genuine bankrupts were to be released from prison. They passed an act for the relief of creditors and poor prisoners. They framed a law for civil marriages and introduced one for the speedier probate of wills. They examined schemes for the ad- vancement of learning and the protection of tenants. They resolved that the Court of Chancery should be abolished, and proposed the ending of tithes and lay presentations to benefices without, however, providing for any considered alternatives (Ashley, 1966: 273). Because of the distrust of lawyers and the old legal system, many of the reforms were impractical, reflecting the tone of the time rather than the needs of the new system. Examples of conserva- tive Parliamentary legislation during the Commonwealth period in- clude strict enforcement of the Sabbath, penalizing swearers and blasphemers, and imposing the death penalty for adultery (Ashton, 1984: 389). Many suggested changes were never implemented, and many others did not survive the Restoration. The fundamental changes can have been summarized by Holdsworth (1956: 429): The King's Bench became the Upper Bench; the Common Pleas remained as before; and it was not till 1657 that the jurisdiction of the court of Exchequer was in any way affected; some of the Palatine jurisdictions were included in the judge circuits; the reform made by the Act of Settlement in the tenure of the judges offices was anticipated when they were appointed during good behavior. But otherwise the machinery of justice worked much as usual. The Commonwealth lasted two years after his death in 1658, and although the bulk of his actions were swept away by the restora- tion, it nonetheless provided a legacy for future generations. Post-Commonwealth England in the mid-seventeenth century, as Hill (1969: 135) has observed, marked the complete end of medieval and Tudor England and marked as well a transition in the relationship between the judiciary and royal authority: The state which Thomas Cromwell had reconstructed in the fifteen-thirties was swept away in 1641--the cen- tral government's power to rule without Parliament, its control over the localities. This revolution in gov- ernment was much more important than that of a century earlier; the old state was not restored in 1660, only its trappings. The prerogative courts did not return, and so the sovereignty of Parliament and common law re- mained. The Privy Council henceforth had no effective control over local government. Taxation and therefore ultimately policy were controlled by Parliament. The Post-Commonwealth Period. The restoration of the monarchy returned Charles II (1660-1685) to the throne, and it was hoped that he would restore the nation. The restoration also assured that Parliament, primarily the House of Commons, exercised control over finances, reducing one cause of social and legal friction. Charles was aided by a national tendency toward conservatism and support of the status quo, which contributed to the stabilization of its power and return to the basic pre-Commonwealth legal machinery. In the years immediately following the restoration, the Crown could do little or nothing by itself except fill offices and carry on the daily administra- tion (Clark, 1965: 3). The inadequacy of judicial staff, the abuses of officials, lack of specificity in defining and protect- ing rights, and the rapid social transformation in which legal ideas and procedures were not correspondingly altered, all of which contributed to the strain on the existing judicial frame- work. There were few legal protections written into post-resto- ration acts, and the legal framework remained unchanged: Although the organization of the legal profession al- tered considerably, no substantial change took place in the law courts. The attempt to substitute the English language for French and Latin in law-books and legal proceeding was abandoned. Nor was there any marked change in the local administration by justices of the peace, though. . .there were changes in municipal cor- porations. The attempts of the law reformers of the first two Stuart reigns to introduce ideas and methods from Roman law and other sources extraneous to the com- mon law of England were not resumed, the more so since the institutions specially favorable to these attempts, the prerogative courts, were not revived. Where the change came about was in the apparatus of central con- trol and in the Parliamentary machine which kept such contact as there was between central control and public opinion (Clark, 1965: 9-10). The power of the peers had declined, the power of the middle class, especially the gentry and merchants, increased. Industri- al power was in transition, shifting both economic activity and population to the north and northwest, realigning economic and political needs and groups. Although over 80 percent of the pop- ulation were still rural, agricultural economy was disintegrat- ing, being replaced by commodity production and exchange, and the importance of capital as the driving force in English economy be- came dominant. Through all of this, the principles of common law and the principles of "fairness" survived the Stewart period. But it was now coupled to the expansion of an autonomous and bu- reaucratic system of rational procedures decoupled from royal in- fluence. Landowners were no longer dependent upon the Crown and gained absolute ownership of their estates. This dramatically altered the status of legal subjects by reducing Crown power, tipping the balance of judicial power in favor of citizens, and created a new legal relationship on which the power of the state was based. Charles was sympathetic to the Catholic Church, and wanted to strengthen the Crown against the overwhelming power of the Anglican party in the Cavalier Parliament by gaining the sup- port of the dissenting Protestant group. This led to an unsuc- cessful combination of political maneuvering and repression in which he resumed anti-dissenter policies. The Habeas Corpus Act of 1679 was perhaps the most significant piece of legislation under Charles. Parliament responded to con- tinuing abuses of the power of arrest and took advantage of the need for conciliation by passing this act, which has been de- scribed "largely a piecemeal repairing of the common law" (Sharpe, 1976: 18). It provided a fundamental guarantee of lib- erty for, in principle, all subjects, and explicitly allowed that neither procedural inadequacy nor unnecessary delays in trials. Following the death of Charles, the short reign of James (1685-1689) produced little except opposition. He was a weak ruler sympathetic to Catholicism, which in a time of colonial ex- pansion threatened by the French and Spanish was intolerable to Protestant economic interests. Unlike Charles, who had attempted to rule the nation through Anglican squires and parsons, James allied himself with the Catholics (Briggs, 1983: 133). In re- sponse to these changes, the Dissenters rebelled and brought from Holland the Protestant William of Orange (1688-1702). Tories and Whigs had dispatched to William of Orange (1689-1694) a request for assistance to aid in restoring their preference for English liberties. William landed in 1688 and marched unopposed to Lon- don. The royal army under James collapsed and the king took ref- uge in Louis XIV's court. The Settlement of 1688-89 preserved the monarchy, and it also reasserted the non-monarchical elements of the constitution. It is under William that the last significant act relevant to our English story was played out in the Bill of Rights (1689). Per- haps the greatest contribution of this Bill lay in the clauses safeguarding the liberty of the individual (Perry and Cooper, 1959). These clauses established in statutory form the protec- tions of the earlier Declaration of Rights, which had been sub- mitted to the new king as a condition of his proclamation ten months earlier. The earlier Act was intended to redress specific grievances that had arisen under the Stuarts, and to clarify le- gal ambiguities of law and liberty. The subsequent Bill of Rights sharply curtailed the prerogative of the sovereign, and perhaps most important, possession of the Crown now became a statutory rather than hereditary right. Increased liberties, re- ligious toleration, protection against arbitrary arrest and rep- resentative taxation were elevated to the status of Law of the Land. Above all, it raised the principles of the Magna Carta and common law as ideological justification these rights, thus bring- ing 500 years of legal history full circle. Discussion The history of the English legal system was uneven and episodic. Some periods were marked by dramatic growth in liberties, others by structural tensions and social conflicts out of which these this growth emerged. But all are interrelated in that they gave rise to ideological, juridical and philosophical transformations that demonstrate the process of legal change. The law of early medieval England emerged from the so-called "dark ages" to maintain the feudal structure of land tenure and military and fiscal obligations. Law was not originally a tool employed so much to "suppress the masses," for this occurred more effectively through military force and cultural domination. Law was rather a means of mediating inter-class conflict among the aristocracy as various groups vied for political or economic pow- er (which in mid-medieval England was often the same thing). The legal history of England, then, was not simply a natural, ra- tional expansion of liberty evolving by some immutable logic of its own. It was a weapon used by diverse groups to challenge, protect, maintain, and otherwise promote social, economic or po- litical advantage and create a world more to their liking. The history of law into the middle of the seventeenth century was the history of men, power and privilege. Women had little role and few rights in this struggle, and law was moved by struggles be- tween and among competing male interests. From its origins in the undeveloped restitutive law of Anglo-Sa- xon England to its further structuring under Edward the Confessor and the Normans, both the legal structure and the content of statutes reflected first a concern with maintaining a preferred set of social relations and only incidentally a concern with ab- stract liberty. Early attempts at central control, such as the witan and similar king's councils, were replaced after the elev- enth century by such bodies as the Curia Regis, King's Council, felonies, and common law. The common law decisions and the new legislative enactments were designed to protect and expand the Crown's power and authority. They also functioned as a steering mechanism to resolve disputes arising from unresolved questions in the feudal system, such as land tenure, inheritance, crown prerogative and reciprocal obligations between Crown and barons. Despite dramatic regional differences in juridical practice in medieval England, these divisions did not, as a rule, have an im- pact on the transformation of law except as a problem of defining judicial jurisdiction as the number of courts increased. Their areas of responsibility became one strategy for acquiring and us- ing courts as a tool in opposing adversaries. Up to the thir- teenth century, legal changes occurred primarily through intra- estate conflict: The clergy, Crown, barons, and rising freeholders and gentry attempted to secure political and economic gains by using law. There were also conflicts reflecting local and individual inter- ests as various courts or administrators jockeyed for increased jurisdiction and resources that would enhance regional advantage or personal careers. The transcendent importance of law as ex- isting above the sovereign, while not fully practiced, was none- theless recognized as at least a tacit operative principle, which meant that even royal policies had to be couched in the legitima- cy, if not in the actual practice, of established legal proce- dures. The growth and development of law emerged, then, not from its own inherent "logic." It was shaped by the tensions between political rivalries and changing social conditions in which old forms of legal practice became inappropriate. To paraphrase Thompson (1975: 260), the old legal forms were bent in order to legitim- ize the status of new land owning and commercial interests. In this sense, Thompson (1975: 261) is correct in arguing the unten- ability of the dogmatic Marxian view that law is an element of superstructure distinct from, but created by, the forces and re- lations of production. Although the law was used to solidify the power of the sovereign, and later the state, it was also used by other groups to chal- lenge state power. Beginning with the Barons who drafted the Magna Carta, both the content and procedures of the legal system were used to limit autonomous power of the Crown, but as these practices became a legitimate force, the underlying ideology be- came a means to justifiy and rationalize state decisions. This chapter has suggested that the appearance of a unified medieval law is a myth; there was continual progress (or process) occur- ring in which law was a useful tool for attempting to create, maintain, or alter power and privilege. The transformation into the industrial age led to a growing number of groups opposing ex- isting social or political relations. These groups found in law either a convenient weapon to expand their rights or a useful protection against abuses of power. The outcome of this was that beginning in the late fifteenth century, law became as much an ideological as a material weapon in conflict. In the 1600s it assumed a partially autonomous status from existing royal author- ity in the 1600s and formed the ideological basis of legal power as a universal and just mediator in resolving disputes. The man- ner in which this fluid, mediating, and double-edged character of law arose during the Middle Ages and changed--and was changed by- -England's industrial revolution subverts the dogmatic Marxian argument that law is wielded primarily by one class to control another: If the law is evidently partial and unjust, then it will mask nothing, legitimize nothing, contribute noth- ing to any class's hegemony. The essential precondi- tion for the effectiveness of law, in its function as ideology, is that it shall display an independence from gross manipulation and shall seem to be just. It can- not seem to be so without upholding its own logic and criteria of equity; indeed, on occasion, by actually being just (Thompson, 1975: 263). The basis of our own legal system was formed from thirteenth and fourteenth century procedures and from the philosophy of rights and corresponding statutes protecting them which arose in the seventeenth. These periods display the relationship between so- cial conflict and legal change. It is against this background that U.S. colonial law, transplanted from England to a land with disparate national cultures, emerged. Although different social forces were operating, the relationship between legal change and conflict remained, and the seeds of our own Constitutional system were planted. It was this legacy which shaped the status of rights possessed by the legal subject, and provided the legal foundation on which contemporary prisoner litigation is based. 5. THE COLONIES, THE CONSTITUTION AND THE "IMPERIAL JUDICIARY" Premise 1: Truth is a 5-4 decision by the Supreme Court (Dan O'Neil, 19** Odds Bodkins). Premise 2: . . .the 1984 term [of the Supreme Court]. . .seemed to produce what one commentator has called a "jurisprudence of idiosyncrasy" (Edwin Meese, III (1985). Conclusion: Truth is idiosyncratic. Law has become one means by which the tension between freedom and social control is mediated. Just as law can be used as a tool for social emancipation, it can also be used for repression. The English judicial concepts and administration that had evolved over the centuries were employed to establish political and eco- nomic domination over its colonies. This created competing defi- nitions of rights and procedures, of judicial and legislative au- thority, and of jurisdiction between England and colonial subjects. The history of our Constitution is thus the history of resistance to repressive law and the effort to define the nature of liberty and the scope of state authority. It has its basis in intra-class conflict, primarily between financial and commercial interests of the two countries, the English attempting to secure advantage through regulatory law, the Colonial opposing such attempts. The previous chapter described how social tensions and subsequent responses shaped the content of law, judicial structure and the concept of individual rights. It also described how the rule of law became partially autonomous became to the state. This section will trace the emergence of the judiciary as a na- tional power, and describe the manner in which not the judiciary, but social conceptions of rights and the status of legal subjects began to change immediately after ratification of the Constitu- tion. When the Barons rebelled against the authority of King John at Runnymede, they drew for ideological inspiration from a distorted and highly romanticized notion of the system of law under Edward the Confessor. Similarly, those who rail against judicial au- thority in the 1980s hold an equally distorted and romanticized conception of the Constitution. Their claims are actually more in line with the principles of the Articles of Confederation than with the Constitution. This chapter describes the emergence of our federal judiciary in order to recognize prisoner litigation as consistent with the judicial philosophy of the writers the Constitution, two centuries of federal judicial practice and a conception of rights that has guided a millennium of jurispru- dence. LEGAL FUNDAMENTALISM U.S. Attorney General Edwin Meese (1985: 7) has expressed hope "for a day when the court returns to the basic principles of the Constitution." His concern, common among judicial conservatives, was over an inaccurate reading of the text of the Constitution and a disregard for the Framers' intention that state and local governments be a buffer against the central- izing tendencies of the national Leviathan (Meese, 1985: 6). The view that current federal judicial decisions, especially in the areas of civil liberties and expansion of rights in criminal proceedings and for the rights of prisoners, represents "bad law." These critics have argued that these rights "make no sense," and has Chief Justice Warren Burger has asked, "If it doesn't make good sense, how can it make good law?" (Duscha, 1969). These critics have argued that the expansion of rights is based on the judiciary's flawed interpretation of both the Con- stitution and of U.S. political history. This chapter challenges this claim: It is the critics, not the so-called "rights indus- try" who have selectively filtered law and events to support their own ideological predilections. Two of the most important principles that provide current justi- fication for the Supreme Court to review prisoner petitions are the duty to protect fundamental Constitutional rights and the right to review at the national level judicial decisions or leg- islative actions taken by individual states. The protection of legal rights by judicial means developed gradually over the cen- turies; the emergence of judicial review, however, is somewhat more recent. Judicial review refers to practice of court review of the deci- sions of other, usually inferior (or lower) court decisions. In the seventeenth century the English practice was expanded to in- clude court review of legislative action as well review of judi- cial decisions. Judicial review originally functioned to pre- serve consistency of court decisions with common law doctrine and to assure the legality of legislation. When the English monarch was sufficiently strong, judicial review of Crown activity was ineffective, and served to legitimate royal authority. When the crown was weak, because of either an ineffective ruler or strong opposition, review served as a moderate check against crown au- thority. In the American colonies, by contrast, there was less opportunity for domination of the judiciary by a single central power, and the history of judicial review developed differently than the English counterpart. Judicial review in the U.S. has evolved into perhaps the single most important means of defining, refining, and protecting legal rights. It is often taken on faith by critics of Supreme Court activism that the original framers did not intend to allow sweep- ing powers of national review of state actions. Contemporary ju- dicial critics who perceive "intrusion" of federal courts into the state domain often argue that such action is actually uncon- stitutional, and allows judges to vote their personal predilec- tions rather than deduce legal principles (Berger, 1977; Bloch, 1958; Glazer, 1975; Morgan, 1984; Meese, 1985). These criti- cisms, however, are based on several mistaken assumptions. jus- tification[31]. First, these critics invariably allude to the Tenth Amendment (1791) to "prove" their thesis: The powers not delegated to the United States by the Constitution, nor prohibited by it to the States, are reserved to the States respectively, or to the people. This has historically been interpreted to mean that no individual state may create or process law in a manner which violates Con- stitutional principles. The Tenth Amendment, however, expressly states, in the clause ignored by Supreme Court critics, that states do not possess powers prohibited by the Constitution: Second, and equally important, to claim that the original framers did not intend for federal review of state law is simply wrong. The early legislative documents and the subsequent activities of the Supreme Court indicate that this function was both intended and implemented in the initial years of the Republic. By recon- structing a romantic interpretation of the so-called "intents" of the original framers, the meaning of broad prescriptions becomes reified and takes on a life independent of what was intended. Such reification serves to distort Constitutional principles and thus translates a political ideology into a judicial philosophy in which the appearance of immutable "truths" are derived from the authority of a "sacred text". Finally, although judicial policy has undergone cyclical shifts over the past two centuries, the history of judicial intervention began in the decades follow- ing ratification of the Constitution and the enactment of the Ju- diciary Act of 1789. These factors tend to be ignored by contem- porary critics of the Supreme Court. This selective perception of historical factors obscures the linear development of the use of courts and law in protecting rights. To better understand both the social and philosophical basis of prisoner rights, it is useful to trace the manner in which rights have been defined and applied in our judicial system. Perhaps the primary issue in the debates over judicial review lies in the role of the federal courts in deciding state matters. Critics claim that intervention disrupts the balance between individual states and the federal government, violates the historic function of the judiciary, and represents an intrusion into affairs of state that the Constitution mandates be left the "the people." Criticisms of prisoner litigation appears especially vulnerable to this argument, since it is argued that federal courts are to distant and too uninformed to decide local law and order issues for state officials." Such criticisms, however, derive from a revision of history based on selective reading of the Constitu- tion, dismissal of the historical antecedents that have shaped current judicial philosophy, and an abysmal ignorance of federal and state legislation that, when violated, provides cause for federal relief in accordance with established law and policy. The three camps in this debate may, for temporary convenience, be divided into federalists, in the twentieth century associated with political liberalism, and anti-federalists. Nationalism is a useful term to identify those who favor a strong central au- thority as a way to unify practices and policies from federalists who still favor a significant degree of state autonomy. Federalists former tend to see the interpretation and application of rights as contingent on the changing needs of society. The federal government is the appropriate and constitutionally-man- dated mechanism for mediating this process. Anti-federalists, by contrast, tend to adopt a romanticized view of rights as they are literally specified in the Constitution, They tend to ignore those factors underlying the practice of rights and reify the literal meaning of the Constitution rather than recognize that meanings are contingent upon the social conditions which exist at the time of interpretation. Anti-federalists are commonly asso- ciated with political conservatism, and feel federal powers should be limited. Using the imagery of "democracy of and by the people," they argue that states alone have the right to make and implement policy. Federalists, by contrast, hold to the view that the Constitution explicitely provides the federal government with the legitimate power and authority to decide those issues that raise a constitutional issue or that contain issues of in- ter-state consequence. Such issues, they argue, are far too im- portant to be decided on the basis of potential regional bias, and require uniform standards consistent with the Law of the Land. As with most debates that are highly emotional and ideo- logically-based, it is difficult to reason people out of a posi- tion into which reason did not lead them. Contemporary anti-fed- eralists speak as though the alleged judicial activism of the past decades is something recent. In a sense, they have re-in- vented the wheel, since this debate simmered in the mid-eight- eenth century, and boiled after the Colonial break with England. Those who lean toward a nationalist perspective view the role of the federal judiciary as breaking down regional or local practic- es. The underlying premise is that in a technologically advanced society, media, transportation, values, and practices become more unified. In this view, diverse local practices may have a disru- putive effect on the social stability, economic growth and cul- ture of the society at large. The central government thus be- comes the "steering mechanism" by which a degree of homogeneity is created and social conflicts resolved (Habermas, 1975; O'Con- nor, 1975). This view recognizes the changing role of the feder- al government in legislative and judicial activity. Hence, in this perspective, a judiciary of "original intent" is a chimera that cannot be attained--even if we wished to--because of the historical forces that have shaped and altered society. THE COLONIAL PERIOD, 1600-1776 Early colonial law did not directly reproduce English law, it nonetheless drew from the English tradition, and both civil and habeas corpus rights of prisoners have been built upon this lega- cy. It also drew heavily from English and French political phi- losophy. In the colonies there was no native political philoso- phy. Justification for rights was drawn from three sources: First, from English and enlightenment philosophy, second, puritan theology and third, was from the requirements of carrying out commerce and industry. The development of colonial law benefited from the emergence of political philosophies that provided the intellectual and ideological justification for individual liberty and weakened the legitimacy of the sovereign as the fount of law. Philosophical ideas articulate rights and are, as a consequence, "living signposts" denoting the status of a particular concept of rights at a specific period of history. In the seventeenth cen- tury, these signposts led legal scholars to develop theories that elevated the individual to greater subject status in relation to the sovereign or state. The seventeenth and eighteenth centuries have become known as the "Age of Reason," in part because of dramatic intellectual activi- ty but also because of attempts to apply rational principles to the governing of society. The seventeenth century English polit- ical philosophy of Thomas Hobbes and John Locke, the eighteenth century French philosophes, and in the late 1700s Thomas Paine and other radical writers combined to influence the rights in the U.S. Constitution, Guided by the writings of Locke, colonists de- veloped a view of limited government in which the primary duty of the central body was to protect the rights of citizens. A gov- ernment that violated this responsibility, as it was perceived the Crown had done in the eighteenth century, lost its legitimacy as a governing body. These political ideas effected subsequent political rights in several ways. First, they created an explicit philosophy for and justification of the expansion of political freedom as fundamen- tal and inviolable to human existence. This extended basic rights to all social subjects, rather than to a privileged few and provided the justification for opposition when infringements occurred. Second, these rights were inalienable, and there was no justification for for their violation. This philosophy con- tinues to have a dramatic impact on twentieth century civil rights law, as some groups, for example prisoners, challenge the rationale by which they have been systematically excluded from Constitutional protections. Third, Seventeenth century legal philosophy altered the conception of the relationship of the state to the subject. While the subject had the obligation to fulfill certain social or political responsibilities, the state, too, had an obligation to protect the citizen. No longer was the extension of rights left to the good will of the sovereign; rights existed independent of the power of any agent to restrict them, and the role of the state became that of protector of rights and mediator in those conflicts which infringed upon them. These ideas influenced the seventeenth century political develop- ment in the American colonies by creating formal structures for implementing and protecting individual liberty. Imported philos- ophy shaped legislation by explicitely delineating the rights and obligations of the state and its subjects. As a consequence, governmental structure was modified to introduce or expand such principles as limitation of state authority, sentative govern- ment, habeas corpus and fair trials. To speak of a homogeneous law in the early American colonies is somewhat misleading, since the Dutch, French, Spanish and English each brought their own customs with them as they settled the new land. As Friedman (1975) has argued, there were as many "coloni- al systems" as there were colonies, and many of the problems of colonial unification centered on the problem of differing legal systems. The English became dominant, however, and they imposed their traditions on the evolving political culture. But even among the English there were disparate legal customs and prefer- ences stemming from diverse religious, economic interests, as well as from the different social needs of each region. Systems of justice began simply and gradually grew more complex, slowly drawing more from the English system as economic and po- litical interdependence grew, and as an expanding population of English settlers were assimilated into what was becoming an in- creasingly common culture[32]. In seventeenth century America, the dominant settlements tended to be run by Puritan clergy, and despite a more-or-less common heritage, the content and practice of justice developed idiosyncratically to meet the particular needs of each community. However, the Puritan grip on the polit- ical and cultural life of the New England colonies had diminished substantially by the early seventeenth century, and by the early eighteenth century, the Puritan doctrine was not a significant factor[33]. Sacred law thus replaced secular law, and English common law became the dominant judicial form. Because of the new conditions and the opportunity to restructure new societies, how- ever, the common law of England was not always applicable to co- lonial conditions. Faced with uncertainty and the need for structure, one of the first tasks of the new colonies was drafting their governing charters. These charters did not create new rights, but rather reaffirmed in written form existing notions of freedom. Colonial charters did not, as a whole, waste space justifying the reasons for claiming rights. The writers assumed that such a rationale was sufficiently obvious, and simply wrote the rights into the documents. The first colonial charter was that of Virginia (1606), which es- tablished the principle that American colonists would have the same rights as English. Subsequent documents were built upon these rights, and all shared one common feature: They established statutory safeguards to individual liberty which were felt to be the basis of English law, even if not fully extended to all sub- jects in England. The king, however, had the authority to ap- prove or reject the charters, but rejection only inflamed the growing political and social tensions between crown and colonies. As a consequence, even though he occasionally vetoed some char- ters or individual provisions, many survived. The Ordinances for Virginia (1618), the charters of Massachusetts Bay (1629), Mary- land (1632), Connecticut (1639), and the Massachusetts Body of Liberties (1641), for example, were drafted prior to comparable English legislation and placed limits on sovereign power and sep- arated their own laws from those of the English. Subsequent charters included religious freedom (e.g., Charter of Rhode Is- land, 1663), basic safeguards in criminal procedures such as tri- al by jury, liberty of conscience, "fair" trials (Concessions and agreements of West New Jersey, 1677), bail (Frame of Government of Pennsylvania, 1682), and right to counsel (Pennsylvania Char- ter of Privileges, 1701). Almost every right in the Constitu- tion's Bill of Rights was safeguarded in two or more of the state Constitutions a century earlier. In fact, the title "Bill of Rights" or "Declaration of Rights" was given by eight states to a separate group of guarantees of liberty and most remaining states inserted protections of human rights among their general provi- sions. The Colonial Legacy It was, then, the colonial legacy drawn from British common law and enlightenment philosophy, rather than particularly new or in- novative home-grown concepts of liberty, that formed the current principles of social and political rights from which contemporary civil rights are drawn. Hence, it is not so much the concept of rights that has changed over the centuries; what has changed is how they are expressed, and how and to whom they will be granted. Despite the fairly uniform acceptance of a similar body of rights in the colonies, their expression was shaped by several basic so- cial factors. First, most colonists were middle class burghers, freeholders and others to whom English agricultural life was fa- miliar (Andrews, 1968). The colonists thus shared a relatively common background and expectations. This, coupled with similar needs for establishing economic and political viability, began to impose some legal homogeneity on diverse social and religious so- cieties. Second, the spirit of Protestant dissent was crucial in defining rights. The doctrine of individual liberty stemmed from the Puritan conception of freedom of speech, assembly and relig- ion. These rights existed in principle under English law, but religious dissenters and political activists found them to be consistently violated, and they wanted explicit protections. One function of the early charters was thus to limit the capacity of a central power to impose a particular set of beliefs on those who did not share the same views of government. Third, the need for economic freedom in commerce, industry and trade required au- tonomy from the restrictive laws which English kings passed in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries in attempts to secure economic advantage. These laws restricted colonial trade and stifled nascent industry, and law itself thus became a focal point of conflict[34]. Fourth, the friction between crown admin- istrative personnel and the colonial bourgeoisie added to the tensions between rulers and ruled. Over-zealous enforcement, military repression, ethnocentrism and administrative abuses exa- cerbated the conflict between ruler and ruled, which further prompted colonists to use law as a way to define rights, even if there was not always corresponding success in fully attaining them. Fifth, the American colonies were faced with a situation similar to that of England a century earlier in that the preroga- tives of the crown were not clearly defined (Pound, 1975: 55), and equally strong claims could be made for either limiting or preserving the crown authority. Finally, Colonial lawyers were united in their opposition to the application of English law to the Colonies, and Pound as identified eight "immemorial rights," guaranteed by centuries of law, that were habitually violated:: (1.) the imposition of taxes on and raising of revenue from the colonies without the consent of the legisla- tive body representing them; (2.) the unification of all powers of government of the colonies in a central- ized administration at Westminster which continually neglected or even positively injured the interests of the colonists in the interest of those who had influ- ence on British politics; (3.) deprivation of jury tri- al by extending admiralty jurisdiction at the expense of the common law; (4.) providing for trials away from the vicinage so as to put parties to expense and anno- yance and deprive them of the advantage of good repute among their neighbors; (5.) infringement of the right to assemble in order to consider grievances and peti- tion the king for redress; (6.) quartering soldiers and keeping a standing army in time of peace without get- ting the consent of the colonial legislature. . . (7.) requiring oppressive security from a claimant of seized property before he could claim it and defend his prop- erty rights. . . (8.) referring to those laws and to instructions to the royal governors as to industries in the colonies, interference with merchants and traders not in time of war, contrary to the interests of the colonies and without any reference to colonial legisla- tures (Pound, 1975: 71-72). In 1768, Parliament established the Courts of Vice-Admiralty in all the colonies for the purpose of more effectively recovering crown revenue. In response, the first Continental Congress drafted The Articles of Association (1775). The Articles called for civil disobedience to British law, and declared that English Crown had extended its powers beyond their ancient limits by de- priving subjects of such rights as trial by Jury (Carson, 1971: 37). This led to the convening of the Continental Congress (1774), the Declaration of Independence (1776) and the Articles of Confederation declaring a "perpetual union" (1777). THE CONSTITUTIONAL PERIOD: 1776-1789 We tend to think of the Constitution as reflecting a single set of ideas, as the product of unified thinkers, or as a set of uni- fied ideas produced in a single voice. This is far from the truth. In fact, the Constitution was the consequence of many diverse voices, of many different ideas, and of different social and political needs. The Constitution was, in short, the product of conflict, compromise negotiation and conciliation. The Articles of Confederation The Articles of Confederation, drafted and accepted by the Conti- nental Congress in 1777, was the first formal document guiding the operation of the new nation. The Articles signified a shift from the colonial to the state system, and were written to pro- tect states from the abuses of a centralized power. Unlike the Constitution, which was placed in supreme position as Law of the Land, Article Two of the earlier document preserved the autonomy of individual states, and subtly placed the national body in a subordinate, and ultimately unworkable, position: ...independence, and every power, jurisdiction, and right, which is not by this confederation, expressly delegated to the United States, in Congress assembled. The Articles were not meant to create a powerful centralized structure superordinate to the new states. The document was in- stead a set of administrative procedures which did not specify rights, but rather established broad working arrangements between the various states. The Articles provided for common currency, common protection and free trade and access between states. They did not, however, provide a useful political philosophy by which to unify or guide diverse groups possessing often incompatible needs, policies or goals. Nor did they provide for a central ex- ecutive department, a federal judiciary, the power to regulate commerce or to prevent discriminatory trade practices, and there was no mechanism to generate revenue. The document contained no national agenda, no specific character, and above all, no cohe- rent political structure for implementation. Above all, there was no provision for a central steering authority that could me- diate the emerging regional commercial problems, a lesson ignored from the experience of medieval England. In some ways the Arti- cles were an antiquated set of principles politically more appro- priate to seventeenth century post-feudal fiefdoms and regional- ism which protected private interests rather than a means of promoting national stability and economic growth. The failure of the Articles prompted a move to draft a new Con- stitution based on a stronger federal system out of which came the document which has lasted to the present. Some observers have contended that the Convention itself was a violation of the Articles' provisions, since the charter should have been altered only by popular vote. A popular election of a convention to amend the Articles would itself have been unconstitutional be- cause the Articles set up a federation which could act only on states, not on individuals. Thus, a popular election would have violated the powers of the document, and at any rate, there ex- isted no clear provision for amending the the Articles written into the document (Brown, 1965: 157). The Constitution. The Constitutional Convention met in Philadelphia in 1787 and adopted the new Constitution. Eight states ratified it in the first year, and the required ninth state, Rhode Island, ratified it in 1788. It went into effect in March, 1789. The Articles of Confederation had generally reflected the philos- ophy of nineteenth century advocates of states' rights and their twentieth century epigones by assuming that the primary protec- tion of liberties would be undertaken by individual state govern- ments Under the Articles, each state retained its sovereignty, freedom, independence, and powers and jurisdiction not rather than a centralized judiciary. expressly delegated to federal au- thority. The Constitution, by contrast, was a fundamental shift away from the regionalism and local autonomy provided for in the Articles, and represented as well a shift from explicit states' rights to a strong central control, and created an estate system with the executive, judiciary and legislature in equal partner- ship. Article III of the Constitution placed judicial power in a single "Supreme Court" and extended this court's authority to all cases "in law and equity" arising under the Constitution. The princi- ple of judicial review of state actions was explicitly estab- lished both in the Constitution itself (see Article III, Sections 1 and 2 and the fourteenth amendment), and in the intents of the legislators as articulated by debates of the Constitutional Con- vention. The ideological debate, however, raged on. Contemporary critics of federal intervention in states' rights in civil matters argue that such authority exceeds the intents of the original framers in defining judicial review. This view is belied by the debates during the Constitutional Convention: .li . . .both sides of the debate conceded the proprie- ty of appellate review over state court decisions, and that a supreme court should be established by the Con- stitution itself. The controversy concerned whether appeal of state court decisions to a national Supreme Court was a sufficient mechanism for insuring national authority and the uniformity of application of federal laws (Barrett and Cohen, 1985: 43). Some states introduced specific proposals to define the relation- ship of the federal judiciary to the states. For example, the Virginia Plan of the Constitutional Convention of 1787 provided for a national judiciary authorized to negate any law that con- travened the principles on which the new Constitution was formed, a principle advocated by many convention participants. The Convention ultimately rejected judiciary veto in favor of ex- ecutive veto, but the ratifyng debates clearly indicate there was certainly no unanimity among the framers in opposition to such judicial powers, and judicial review was in fact provided for in subsequent Constitutional language. This power is implied in the "Supreme Law of the Land" doctrine specified in Article VI which states that the Constitution . . .Shall be the supreme Law of the Land; and the Judges in every State shall be bound thereby, any Thing in the Constitution or Laws of any State to the Contrary notwithstanding. The Constitutional powers of federal courts were further clari- fied by the Judiciary Act of 1789 (1 Statutes at Large, 72). This Act provided that the power to review and act upon the deci- sions of state courts lay explicitely with the Supreme Court in several types of cases, including those in which decisions or laws were "repugnant to the constitution, treaties or laws of the United States," or when laws or decisions clearly violated a Con- stitutional principle (Barrett and Cohen, 1985: 44). The Act further established the principle of judicial review by the Su- preme Court for both federal and state courts. The Act provided for a Supreme Court and six justices, and as a concession to those who wanted assurances that state and regional law would be preserved, district courts were established within each state. The Act authorized all federal courts to issue various writs, such as habeas corpus, and further specified that all federal courts possessed the power to grant new trials. Although this Act has been amended and modified in the past two centuries, it provides the fundamental framework by which the judiciary oper- ates to this day, and offers irrefutable evidence against those who claim that recent Courts have usurped powers originally in- tended by framers of the Constitution. Constitutional rights and procedures were quickly accepted, and they established a firm philosophy on which to build a national judiciary. The basic principles included the following: (1.) the idea of a fundamental law, the "law of the land," to which all official and governmental action was bound to conform, which law was to be applied by the courts in the course of orderly litigation accord- ing to the common law, and could be invoked against of- ficials by anyone aggrieved; (2.) the idea of immemori- al rights of Englishmen, secured by the law of the land, and of the common law in which they were recog- nized as the birthright of Englishmen and so of Ameri- cans. . . (3.) the idea of authoritative declarations of these rights in charters and bills of rights. . . (4.) the idea of an independent judiciary, as set forth in the English Bill of Rights of 1688, to administer the fundamental law, and of lawmaking by a body dis- tinct from the executive; (5.) the idea of courts re- fusing to apply statutes in contravention of fundamen- tal law (Pound, 1975: 61-62). This did not mean that conflicts between federalists and anti- federalists were resolved, however. The question of states' rights remained a smoldering issue in national politics. The Virginia and Kentucky Resolutions of 1798-99 aimed at the Alien and Sedition acts typified the concerns of anti-Federalists. The Sedition Act (1798) was passed by federalists to curtail politi- cal speech which attacked government policy during a period of tense relations with France. The Virginia General Assembly ar- gued this was an intrusion of federal power on state domain, and passed a protest "against the palpable and alarming infractions of the Constitution," arguing that such powers were "positively forbidden" by the amendments. The Alien and Sedition Acts were never tested in the courts, but they surely would have survived under the federalist-controlled judiciary at the turn of the cen- tury. Despite their expiration, they provided a precedent for repression of "undesirable" political activity that survived through World War I and the Palmer Raids of 192*. The stakes in the states' rights debate were political power rather than juridical principle, and the southern states espe- cially argued for state supremacy because of its politically weaker position in relation to the north. The South was solidly agricultural, while the north was developing a strong infrastruc- ture based on industry, finance and commerce. The federalists dominated the judiciary and the legislature, and southern states perceived themselves, not without considerable justification, to be politically subservient to their northern neighbors. The slavery issue periodically re-emerged during the War of 1812, generally raised by the entry of new states into the union. The ban on the importation of slavery in 1808 aggravated these re- gional tensions, although over a quarter of a million slaves were illegally imported up to the civil war. The principles of federalism dominated the language and implemen- tation of, the Constitution; nonetheless, the Document represent- ed a compromise between two competing positions. One school, later to be articulated in Antifederalist philosophy, saw the new government as a potential de- stroyer of the rights of states. This group wanted federal law to be adjudicated first by state courts and only on appeal by the United States Supreme Court. The other school, represented by Hamilton and Madison, feared that the parochial prejudice of the state courts would deal unjustly with litigants from other states and other countries. . . A compromise on court organi- zation was reached: Federalists obtained lower federal courts, and antinationalists placed them within "state containers" (Richardson and Vines, 1970: 22). The Federalist Papers are revealing for providing insights into the intents of the original framers. Hamilton, especially, ar- gued that the federal government's role was, in part, to assure that state legislatures were to be limited by constitutional pro- visions, thus providing at least some basis for the argument that the U.S. Supreme Court properly has jurisdiction over state crim- inal and civil procedures dealing with constitutional issues (FP: 475). He considered the Constitution to be the standard for the construction of state law (FP, 482), and although he, like most others, believed in limited government, it was presumed that the Constitutional principles would apply to the states. One way of assuring some consistency, it was felt, was to establish federal district courts in each state. But it was clear that individual state courts were to be reasonably autonomous, but that federal courts were the proper forum for appeal for questions of appro- priate jurisdiction. Hamilton also argued recognized the inter- dependence of law when he argued that all legislatures should look beyond their own borders to the legal principles of other jurisdictions, even of other countries (FP: 493). Hence, the original intents were, at least for some of the framers, not nar- row or parochial, but global and extensive. It has been argued that our Constitution embodies the interests of a dominant class. Since government is primarily concerned with making rules to determine property relations, the classes whose rights are to be determined must obtain from the government the rules which will favor their economic interests. Thus constitutional history becomes the process by which various economic groups seek to pro- tect their particular interest by making or altering the fundamental law of the land (Brown, 1965: 27). In his useful but flawed class-based interpretation, Beard (1965) has observed that the constitution was established by personal property interests or capitalistic classes as opposed to small farmers and debtors. Beard did not argue, as many think he did, that the division in the country was between the owners of prop- erty, who favored the Constitution, and the propertyless, who op- posed it. The split was more subtle: Between personality or per- sonal property (e.g., movable assets, a concern of merchants and bankers, and realty (e.g., land), a concern of small farmers and debtors[35]. But as Brown (1965: 113) has observed, one of the most striking features of the debates was the fact that practically every fea- ture of the Constitution was subjected to the question of whether "the people" would accept it. Contemporary critics of judicial power perceive modern judicial theory to be based on a theory of centralization which, at least until the Burger court, has elevated the judiciary to what some see as the most influential of the three governmental branches. The beginnings of "law by national judiciary" were framed in this first Constitutional period. The definitive scope of this power, however, remains debated to this day, contributing to considera- ble disagreement over how far the Supreme Court may or ought to go in pursuing its original mandate. Following Goldman and Jah- nige (1985: 231), we can trace five broad historical cycles in U.S. political and judicial history. These were 1) the federal- ist-Jeffersonian (1789-1828); 2) the Jacksonian (1828-1860); 3) the First Republican (1860-1896); 4) the Second Republican (1896-1932); and 5) the New Deal (1932-1968). A sixth, which we might label The Retrenchment Era, began with the election of Richard Nixon in 1968 and has been more-fully implemented in the 1980s by the Reagan administration. Each of these periods was shaped by broader social and political forces, and each illus- trates shifts in the role and function of the court and helps ground the emergence of prisoner litigation in a historical con- text. THE FEDERALIST-JEFFERSONIAN PERIOD (1789-1828) Current Constitutional activity reflects a long process in the transformation of legal theory, and this transformation began im- mediately following the Constitution's ratification. The feder- alist-Jeffersonian judicial period contains, as Goodman and Jah- nige (1985: 231) have observed, two distinct sub-phases. First was a period Constitutional consolidation, as the Supreme Court cautiously defined its jurisdiction and the scope of its legal and political powers. The guiding theories of such early Consti- tutional theorists as James Wilson and John Marshall held that the relationship between states and the federal judiciary was based on the federalist theory of separation and balance of pow- ers and upon the distribution of power among three co-equal com- ponents. The second phase, from 1800-1828, was that of Jefferso- nian democracy. Guided by the Federalist Chief Justice John Marshall, the courts consolidated judicial power--and thus the Constitution--as the supreme Law of the Land. Despite apparent differences, these two phases .li . . .still had the overall unity of the federal government under the control of a fairly select elite of merchants and planters concerning itself with the problems of Constitution building, union, and the cre- ation of economic and political stability in the face of intrigues and tensions both foreign and domestic (Goodman and Jahnige, 1985: 231). In both phases, the Supreme Court faced the problem of defining the scope of the powers of the new federal government, as well as the relationship of its own power and goals in relation to both the national executive and legislative branch on one hand, and the new states on the other. Banks, transportation companies, and other enterprises that operated between states raised numer- ous legal and federally-related questions that had never been en- countered previously. As a consequence, the subject status of corporations and their relationship to the national government became an issue. Could a corporation based in one state but op- erating in several be taxed by those states, or only by the host state? Could the federal government intervene in interstate com- merce? Could corporations or states enact policies or laws that would effectively put the federal government in a subordinate po- sition to corporations? The judiciary resolved virtually all of these issues in a way that assured strong federal control and a social and political environment conducive to national commercial interests, and Was the status of a corporation of one state set up in another sub- ject to the laws of the home or host state? It was generally ruled that corporations, although not "persons," nonetheless held certain rights beyond its mere corporate character, and the fed- eral government had regulatory and statutory priority over the states. Three early Supreme Court decisions typify how the Supreme Court helped solidify federal power. Marbury vs. Madison (5 U.S. ((1 Cranch)) 137, 1803), established the principle of judicial re- view; Fletcher vs. Peck (10 U.S. ((6 Cranch)) 87, 1810) estab- lished the inviolability of contracts, placing them beyond the reach of state courts; and McCulloch vs. Maryland (17 U.S. ((4 Wheaton)) 316, 1819)) affirmed the doctrine of precedence of fed- eral rights. Marbury v. Madison grew out of federalist opposition to central- ized power and attempts to pack the national judiciary through John Adams' appointment of "midnight judges"--so called because their commissions of appointment were rushed through in the final hours of the his outgoing administration. Supreme Court judges, solidly federalist, unanimously declared unConstitutional the Re- publican attempt to interfere with the appointments. This deci- sion solidly established the centralized and semi-autonomous pow- er of the court in its first decades, and defined the federal government's obligations in mediating social tensions through systematic use of law, power, and resources. Marshall held that the judiciary was the final interpreter of the Constitution, and in skirting sensitive political issues, he also established the framework and early legitimacy for an "activist" court (Thomas, 1976: 18-22). Marshall concluded that no original powers could be vested in the Supreme Court beyond those to which the Court was restricted by the Constitution (Carlson, 1971: 217). Al- though Marshall disclaimed all jurisdiction not given by the Con- stitution or by federal law, he invoked the 14th section of the Judiciary Act of 1789 which permitted "original suits" to be brought before the Supreme Court, and established the principle that the court itself could determine the nature of federal pow- ers in the Constitution. The significance of this decision lies in the reasoning by which it established the dominance of federal judicial power as ultimate arbiter of Constitutional questions and established as well the Supreme Court as an equal among the Executive and Legislative branches of government. The second decision, Fletcher v. Peck, was the first case in which the Supreme Court ruled a state statute to be in conflict with the constitution. The issue centered on a land contract which the state of Georgia had rescinded over a previous approv- al, and involved a land scandal (Yazoo land fraud) and bribery by two U.S. senators and three prominent judges, including a Supreme Court justice. This decision was important for two reasons: It was the first time that an important state statute was voided by the Supreme Court for violating the "general principles" of the Constitution. Second, as Miller (1982: 66) has observed, for the first time the Supreme Court "invented law," since there were no judicial precedents or legislative policies to guide decision making. The war of 1812 marks a transition period in U.S. history, in part because national priorities shifted, and in part because the war created a social climate analogous in many ways to the 1980s. The war of 1812 was costly by standards of the time; it dislocat- ed business and foreign trade, raised the national debt consider- ably, debased currency values, and exposed glaring cracks in the national political facade (Nye and Morpurgo, 1965: 337). After the war, the public was less interested in external foreign rela- tions and more in expanding the territory and economic structure of country. The post-war period of 1814-1828 was known as the "era of good feelings," so-called because, as in the 1980s, the country was "feeling good" about itself. There was a trend to- ward ultra-nationalism, characterized by the Monroe Doctrine, a stronger military, solid uniform national currency, a protective tariff for industry, rapid construction of infrastructure (roads, bridges, canals), and territorial expansion. It was an age of the business entrepreneur, expanding industry (textiles, steel, transportation), and finance. Republicans strengthened the doc- trine of nationalism in political and commercial enterprise, fa- cilitated by the Supreme Court. The trend toward a strong feder- al system continued to which the Supreme Court contributed, as the third case, McCulloch v. Maryland, illustrates. McCulloch addressed the status of a national bank, which had been a controversial topic for a quarter-century. Two basic questions were raised: 1) The constitutionality of an act incorporating the Bank of the United States, and 2) the power of a state to tax an agency of the federal government. Marshall's decision acknowl- edged the limits of federal powers, while also leaving the feder- al government with the discretionary powers to determine the means by which it would carry out its functions. The decision prohibited the states' right to tax federal agencies on the grounds that if one agency could be taxed by states, then so could all other federal enterprise. This last decision held that the federal government is granted powers even if they are not specifically stated in the Constitution if those purpose of its acts are consistent with the Constitution and in the national in- terest. This early ruling explicitely defined the relationship of individual states as subordinate to the federal judiciary, thus establishing the principle of federal supremacy. Marshall reminded posterity that the Constitution was a living document capable of meeting the various crises of human affairs. If judicial expansion of national powers necessarily "erodes" the powers of the states, then the Marshall court should be recog- nized as the first cycle of this erosion. These three decisions typified how, through judicial means, the federal government slowly established supremacy over the states from the inception of the Constitution. It was done by integrating the original philosophy and intents of the framers with the unforeseen needs of a growing economic and political system. These original deci- sions, which provided the precedents and judicial philosophy of late-twentieth century federal court activity were well within, rather than outside of, the language and purpose of the Constitu- tion. As Wolfe (1982) has argued, Marshall was faithful to the Constitution, and carefully carved his decisions from the intents of the founders of "democratic constitutionalism." When seen in this light, the legal theories on which federal courts base their intervention in prison affairs is not merely the result of civil rights activists or "idiosyncratic law," but has deep roots in our early Constitutional history. THE JACKSONIAN PERIOD (1828-1860) The Era of Good Feeling was spawned by nationalist pride, promot- ed by federal politicians and served primarily the interests of the growing economic interests of the northeast. But after 15 years of growing nationalism, there occurred a backlash. In 1828 the Democrats elected popular war hero Andrew Jackson to the first of his two terms as president. Jackson contributed little to the movement which bears his name, however, and the He served mostly as a symbol of broader social forces (Nye and Morpurgo, 1965: 380). A political pragmatist rather than a doctrinaire ideologue, Jackson campaigned against Jeffersonian Democracy and what he perceived as the minority rule of northeastern financiers and industrialists. Jackson led an attack on national institu- tions, especially banks and the Supreme Court, which he felt were tools by which the powerful minority maintained its position. He departed radically from what has become known as Jeffersonian De- mocracy, which dominated the previous two decades of U.S. poli- tics and government. Jefferson's political philosophy, like Jackson's, was based on a form of agrarianism. But Jefferson's philosophy was more appropriate to a non-expanding society and economy. Although Jefferson had opposed unrestrained centralized power as inimical to democracy, he and his followers nonetheless believed in, and created the political structure for, a strong national authority as a means to develop commerce and finance. Jackson, by contrast, developed policies based on expanding land values, diversified agriculture, and speculative opportunities: To Jackson, the federal government was not simply a po- liceman to keep order, but a parent who gave a helping hand when it was needed--but only when the citizen asked for it. The Jacksonian did not want the govern- ment to control his affairs except to the degree that he requested it to do so. He was never loath (nor were the Grangers and Populists later) to call on Washington for assistance, for roads, canals, credit or subsidies; yet at the same time he fiercely resented any intrusion of federal power into his own domain of authority (Nye and Morpurgo, 1965: 384). Jackson's influence on the judiciary was considerable. The Jef- fersonian-Federalist era had been dominated by Chief Justice Mar- shall, and was characterized by decisions that strengthening both the federal government and the judiciary; Jacson reversed this. During his eight years, Jackson was able to appoint five of the then-sitting seven justices, including elevation of his friend Roger T. Taney to the position of Chief Justice, although not without considerable difficulty in his confirmation hearings. Although not judicially timid, Taney guided the court to a mid- dle-of-the road position, tended to side with Southern states on states' rights issues, particularly slavery and commerce. By at- tempting to placate Southern political concerns while ignoring their underlying sources, the Supreme Court sank "into obscurity and impotence" from which it did not emerge until after the civil war. To some, the Taney court was archetypically conservative because of its support of business interests and willingness to stamp ap- proval upon legislative and executive policy. Others view it as a liberal activist court for its decisions which extended long- term judicial power. Much like the Burger Court of the later twentieth century, the Taney court defies easy classifications, illustrating how difficult it can be to precisely categorize the political stance of the judiciary. The most far-reaching of these decisions was the Dred Scott decision (Scott v. Sandford, S.C. 19 Howard, 393-633, 1857), the first major civil rights case in U.S. judicial history. It involved not only the issues of slavery, legislative jurisdiction and judicial power, but in- volved as well the subject status of slaves and the Constitution- al rights such a status conferred. The Court's decision reaf- firmed the supremacy of judicial power even while promoting, in the short run, states' rights. At issue in the Scott case, os- tensibly over the legal status of a slave, was actually an ideo- logical struggle over the Missouri Compromise. The Missouri Com- promise (1820) had been intended by Congress to settle the politically sticky question of slavery. It permitted slavery in Missouri, but prohibited it to the west of the Mississippi River and in portions of the Louisiana Territory to the north of Mis- souri. Because of this Act, Southern politicians hesitated to admit additional free states, correctly perceiving that it would shift the balance of power to the North, especially to abolition- ists. Southerners contended that the compromise was unconstitu- tional, and it was repealed by the Kansas-Nebraska Act (1854), which, among other provisions, left the issue of slavery to the voters of individual states. The repeal satisfied most Southern- ers, but many abolitionist politicians were outraged, and the po- litical harmony of the nation was threatened. The Scott decision was an attempt to provide a Constitutional balance between the two positions, but it satisfied neither. Dred Scott, the plaintiff, was a Missouri slave who was taken by his owner to the free states of Illinois and Wisconsin, where he married and resided with his family and owner from 1834-36. Scott's supporters sued for his freedom in Missouri courts. They claimed that under the provisions of the Missouri Compromise he was legally emancipated because he and his family had resided sufficiently long in free territory. After years of litigation and see-saw decisions in Missouri state and federal district courts, the case finally came before the Supreme Court in 1856, but a decision was postponed until the following year to avoid making it an election year issue. When the case was finally de- cided, Chief Justice Taney identified two primary legal issues: 1) whether the court had jurisdiction in the case (the court ruled it did), and 2) whether, on the merits of the case, Scott was indeed "free." The court ruled against Scott on the latter issue. Ironically, this case had minimal impact on Scott. He was emancipated immediately after the decision by his owner--the brother-in-law of the deceased original owner--who was elected to state office as an abolitionist (Lewis, 1965). Taney's legal logic in writing the majority opinion has often been questioned, but the significance of the outcome should not be overlooked. This decision, while satisfying to conservatives, had profound long-range consequences for twentieth century liber- alism. Some consider the Dred Scott decision to be the founda- tion of contemporary judicial activism because the Supreme Court for the first time arrogated to itself (and to every other feder- al court) the right to settle socio-political conflicts by judi- cial decision, thus dramatically increasing judicial and politi- cal power of the judiciary (Boudin, 1968: 3). In addition to attempting to mediate the slavery question, Taney also attempted to balance national and state commercial inter- ests. The focus of litigation during his tenure had shifted to ships, bridges, land, or canal companies, and banks (Boudin, 1968: 15). His "Cooley Rule" (Cooley v. Board of Wardens of the Port of Philadelphia, 52 U.S. ((12 Howard)) 299, 1851) stemmed from a conflict between state and federal regulation of commer- cial transportation, and typifies the philosophy of Taney's court toward business. At issue was the degree to which states could regulate commerce (in this case water transportation). While ac- knowledging and not repudiating the scope of federal jurisdiction in regulating commerce specified in the Judiciary Act of 1789, Taney also recognized the right of individual states to regulate matters in their immediate interest. The decision was intended to be limited in scope, but in practice it struct a temporary balance between states' rights and federal powers and slowed the trend toward judicial nationalism. It granted partial powers to states to regulate interstate commerce on one hand, while on the other made clear that it was the Court, not congress, that would define which commerce could be regulated by the states and which demanded a single uniform rule (Miller, 1982: 69). Taney remained Chief Justice until the close of the Civil War. During this period, the Court's judicial philosophy shifted away from expansion of court powers of judicial review, which charac- terized the Marshall court, to a more moderate position. The court also ruled, in Barron v. Baltimore (7 Pet. 243, 1833), that the first ten amendments applied only to federal, and not state, courts, which limited the scope of federal jurisdiction until af- ter the Civil War. Taney led a trend, begun in the 1820s, which slowed, but did not reverse, the tide of nationalism. His court functioned in part to mediate those political and economic inter- ests that had not fully benefited from the growth of the first decades of the new Republic, and a court that became known for its judicial restraint nonetheless took an activist role in de- ciding political issues in favor of a preferred definition of so- cial order. Judicial doctrine and political dogma coincided, and the court explicitely assumed the powers to mediate conflict, and has retained them since. At the close of the Jacksonian era, the country had changed dra- matically from the isolated agricultural and small business structure dominant during the Colonial era. Slave labor account- ed for nearly 30 percent of the U.S. labor force (Aronowitz, 1973: 145), and the composition of the skilled working class had shifted. After 1850, native born artisans who had dominated their crafts prior to the Revolution remained; Western European skilled immigrants moved into the textile, mining and iron indus- try; displaced farmers moved into urban areas; and Irish and Chi- nese peasants appeared en-masse to fill unskilled positions (Aro- nowitz, 1973: 146). For Blacks, especially after the civil war, this led to intense competition for economic status in the labor groups, and the legal and political infrastructure did not match the changes required to pursue "life, liberty and happiness." This changed dramatically after the Civil War. THE FIRST REPUBLICAN PERIOD (1860-1896) The Civil War era marks the beginning of a dramatic shift in the political and judicial history of civil rights. By 1860, politi- cal and regional conflict had shattered former party alliances, and the once-dominant Whigs and Democrats suffered internal ten- sions and were no longer an effective political force. The Kan- sas-Nebraska Act (1854) had split the Democrats along regional lines; Southern Democrats supported the act, Northern Democrats and abolitionists were virulently opposed. The Republicans had opposed the Kansas-Nebraska act. in 1860, the Republican presidential candidate, Abraham Lincoln, won in a four-way race with less than half the popular vote. The election of Republicans, and thus of representatives of Northern political and economic interests, led to the final breach in the Union, and ultimately to secession of the Southern states. For the next quarter century, the Republicans solidified national po- litical control, and dominated the Supreme Court through succes- sive appointment of two Chief justices, both from Ohio, and a stream of Republican justices. Among the issues brought before the court were property and voting rights, interstate commerce, and the seemingly never-ending question of the status and rights of business. During the civil war, the federal judiciary had stayed out of the way of the federal legislative and executive branches (Miller, 1982: 73), and the Supreme Court was relatively quiescent, although it did review war related cases. The Supreme Court was, for example, called upon to specifically define the conflict. Was it a war, a rebellion, or an insurrection? A def- inition was necessary for dealing with military blockades, sei- zure of foreign and domestic ships, and especially for resolving secessionist issues after 1865. It was ruled that the Rebellion was only an insurrection, that there was no de facto Government possessing legal efficacy and recognition thus could not be ex- tended to the pretended government of th Confederacy. The decade following the war has been called the "zenith of fed- eralism" (Carson, 1971: 501). and the judiciary made it clear that it had exclusive authority to review the Constitutionality of state policy on national issues. Post-war political schisms had not disappeared, and one function of the federal government was to steer the social system through potentially disruptive conflicts that threatened to disrupt the fragile harmony of re- construction. The federal government used its status as military victor to reunite the states and define and implement a national agenda, **MISSING TEXT??** The problems of re-unification, economic development along capi- talist-industrial rather than agricultural-slavery models, and the protection of freed slaves occupied considerable federal leg- islative and judicial attention. Two issues dominated the judi- ciary: First was reconstruction and civil rights. The civil status of former slaves and of Northern free Blacks in Southern territory, the dissolution of the Southern system of agricultural labor and the relationship of all Blacks to the Constitution de- manded immediate attention. Second was the increasing problem of regulating commerce and industry. This issue centered on whether the Constitution permitted government to counter the growing po- litical and economic power of increasingly large businesses (trusts). Secondary post-war issues included land claims, such as and Spanish laws under Louisiana Treaty were also common (Car- son, 1971: 384). Other issues included questions of land, taxes, internal improvements, industrial expansion, finances, tariffs, labor and contract. The Republicans were divided on Reconstruction policy; the Radi- cal Republicans favored harsh penalties and corresponding legis- lation, and the moderates, led by President Johnson, favoring a more lenient policy[36]. The radicals advocated numerous poli- cies for expanding the rights of Blacks, but their so-called "Negro Policy" was cynical and politically motivated, devised as a means to increase Black Republican voters to allow Republican control of government. Obedient Blacks would vote, influential Southern anti-Federalist whites would not. The election of 1866 returned a majority of Radical Republicans to Congress, and this group led the enactment of post-war civil rights legislation and Constitutional Amendments. CIVIL RIGHTS AND THE CIVIL WAR AMENDMENTS Following the war, a concept of civil rights emerged in a form which survives to this day. This occurred at first primarily through congressional legislation designed explicitely to protect individual rights, that operated on a national scale. In 1866, the Ku Klux Klan had been secretly formed to preserve the "white race" by terrorizing Blacks. It was thus judged by Northern pol- iticians that Constitutional amendments would be useful to create rights for Blacks, and legislation was enacted to protect these newly-created rights. The most important piece of legislation was entitled "Act to Protect all Persons in the United States in their Civil Rights (1866)," intended to protect freed slaves from potential civil rights abuses. The first formal attempt at en- forcement was instituted by Executive Document #29 (19 February, 1867) when President Johnson, acting on an earlier resolution by the Senate, directed the Attorney General to report possible vio- lations of the Act. Act. The first case filed under this legis- lation was on behalf of William Fincher, "a person of color in the state of Georgia," who alleged he was illegally indicted and convicted for vagrancy in Pike County and forcibly subjected to involuntary chain gang labor, a condition which violated his Con- stitutional and statutory civil rights. Fincher claimed his prosecution was intended to destroy his influence and credibility in the community as a "colored preacher" because he was "zealous- ly attached" to a society which was "offensive to public senti- ment" (Executive Document #29, 1867: 3). A second civil rights act was passed by Congress in 1867, but was vetoed by President Johnson. Shortly after the ratification of the 14th amendment (1868) which extended Constitutional protec- tions from the federal domain to the states, the last significant civil rights enactment of the reconstruction era was passed in 1871. This so-called "Ku Klux Klan Act" survives today as 42 U.S.C. Section 1983, and although it did not create rights, it provided civil cause of action enforceable in federal courts against any state official found to be in violation. Although modified and renewed several times in the next 10 years, the rel- evant language of the original civil rights legislation today re- mains essentially unchanged. In addition to legislative acts, three amendments were added to the Constitution. The first was the thirteenth amendment (1865). Its first section held that: Neither slavery nor involuntary servitude, except as a punishment for crime whereof the party shall have been duly convicted, shall exist within the United States, or any place subject to their jurisdiction. The thirteenth amendment was significant not only for its sub- stance, but for the new political philosophy it reflected: The federal government assumed responsibility for guaranteeing liber- ty by nationalizing the right to freedom and enforcing this right through "appropriate legislation," a term inserted into the Con- stitution for the first time. The policies of reconstruction, however, were necessarily lenient, thus allowing latitude for considerable political autonomy in previously successionist states. This allowed the former slave-holding states opportunity to impose restrictive laws particularly against Blacks. The Fourteenth Amendment Prior to the civil war, it had been settled that the federal gov- ernment lacked the power to apply federal Bill of Rights stan- dards to individual states. The Supreme Court had earlier estab- lished in Barron v. Baltimore (7 Pet. 243, 1833) that these provisions were limited to the federal government only. Subse- quent attempts to expand Constitutional protections to state ac- tions through, for example, the "due process" clause of the Fifth Amendment, repeatedly failed. Failure prompted remedy, and addi- tional legislation was required in order to provide the federal judiciary with explicit powers to enforce federal law in the states[37]. Fearing that additional protections were required to protect rights, Congress passed the fourteenth amendment in 1868. The fourteenth amendment was the most significant of the civil rights amendments, for it not only defined citizenship and prohibited states from enacting laws which abridged Constitutional rights, but also extended federal authority into what had previously been non-federal jurisdiction. Proposed in 1866 and ratified in 1868, its language continues to provide the basis for in civil rights litigation[38]: All persons born or naturalized in the United States, and subject to the jurisdiction thereof, are citizens of the United States and of the State in which they re- side. No State shall make or enforce any law which shall abridge the privileges or immunities of citizens of the United States; nor shall any State deprive any person of life, liberty, or property, without due pro- cess of law; nor deny to any person within its juris- diction the equal protection of laws. The successionist states were not represented in the voting[39]. This amendment was intended to protect newly-freed slaves in the Southern states, but its language was broad, and there was no reference to slavery or to any specific group. The first sen- tence of Section I of the Fourteenth Amendment has become known as the "citizenship clause." It provided not only the definition of citizenship which justified extension of Constitutional rights to Blacks, but implicitly extended these rights to other ethnic groups as well. Some of these groups, however, would not receive the benefits for until the next century. The second sentence, the "due process" clause, remains controversial to this day. In essence, it extended to Bill of Rights to the state. The "equal protection" clause further granted to all citizens Constitutional safeguards--in principle, at least--against discriminatory law. Because the language pertained to any person, and because of what has come to be known as the "Due Process clause," the fourteenth amendment is considered the most important single act in promot- ing the federal government to the supreme protector of liberty in state actions. Even today it remains debated whether this was intended to be a short-hand summary of the bill of rights en- forceable by the federal judiciary upon the states (Berger, 1977). The final amendment of the reconstruction period was the fif- teenth (1870), which was intended to protect voting rights: The right of the citizens of the United States to vote shall not be denied or abridged by the United States or by any State on account of race, color, or previous condition of servitude. The issues surrounding the Amendments and legislation reflected issues that had surged into the political domain in the 1840s. They included such problems as habeas corpus law, slavery, fugi- tive slaves, the "morality" of state law, the powers of the fed- eral government to review state statutes, and the balance of po- litical power between federal and state governments. The debates were formulated in the abstract language of Constitutional mean- ing and philosophy, and taken as a whole reflect two incompatible interpretations of the relationship between federal and state tone[40]. For example, some Southern states jailed Northern Blacks, particularly sailors, because of laws excluding Blacks from the state. This was considered a gross violation of Consti- tutionally protected rights by Northern politicians. Arguing the case in congress, Daniel Webster, a Massachusetts Senator and ar- dent Federalist, summarized the tone in an 1850 Senate debate: There is a more tangible and irritating cause of grie- vance at the North. Free blacks are constanty employed in the vessels of the North, generly as cooks or ste- wards. When the vessel arrives, these free colored men, are taken on shore, by the police or municipal au- thority, imprisoned, and kept in prison, till the ves- sel is again ready to sail. This is not only irratat- ing, but exceedingly inconvenient and practice, and seems altogether unjustifiable, and oppressive. . . The North thinks such imprisonment illegal, and uncon- stitutional (Virginia Commission on Constitutional His- tory: 2). A South Carolonia Senator responded in defense of such law and practice by arguing that states could do as they pleased: The laws of Congress, enacted long ago, for the regula- tion of commerce and navigation, nowhere regard a col- ored man as a citizen, and have made a makred distinc- tion between them; neither the Constitution nor the ancient laws regarded a colored man as a citizen, with- in the contemplation of that term; and so far as it re- gards this species of persons, each State can give them a local status, to which all coming within a State ju- risdiction must assimilate. They are a species of per- sons having such rights only as may be conferred upon them by State jurisdiction; they have no federal eligi- bility, or federal recognition, as citizens of the United States (Virgina Historical Commission, 1967: 2). The controversy over the source of authority by which an entire category of persons would be defined as "legal subjects," and thus entitled to corresponding federal protections was clearly understood as ultimately a Constitutional question. Nineteenth century legislators, like their twentieth century counterparts, were divided on the question of whether the Constitution was an instrument of justice by which the nation's citizens were to be protected from injustice, or whether the Constitution was instead primarily a regulatory device limited to administering activities between the states and between private individuals and the feder- al body. Northern politicians clearly opted for the former in- terpretation, and argued that it was within the federal domain to establish protectings binding on individual states. Typical of the arguments is that of James Wilson when supporting the House version of the Civil RIghts Act of 1866: As I have already said, "If the citizens of the United States, as such, are entitled to possess and enjoy the great fundamental civil rights which it is the true of- fice of the Government to protect, and to equality in the exemptions of the law, we must of necessity be clothed with the power to insure to each and every cit- izen these things which belong to him as a constituent member of the great national family." Whatever these great fundamental rights are, we must be invested with power tolegislate for their protection or our Constitu- tion fails in the first and most important office of Government. . . . . Before our Constitution was formed, the great fundamental rights which I have mentioned, belonged toevery person who be- came a member of our great national family. No one surrendered a jot or a tittle of these rights by con- senting to the formation of the Government. And these sevesral departments of Government possess the power to enace, administer, and enforce the laws "necessary and proper" to secure these rights which existed anterior to the ordination of the Constitution. Any other view of the powers of this Government dwards it and renders it a failure in its most important office (Virginia Commission on Constitutional History, 1967: 164-165). In response, New Jersey states' rights Democrat Andrew Rogers summarized the position of position of the opponents of federal powers: Now, sir, it cannot be pretended by any lawyer in this House, whatever his political opinions may be, who will base his integrity upon his professional experience, that there is any authority in the Congress of the United States to enter the domain of a State and inter- fere with its internal police, statutes, and domestic regulations (Virginia Commission on Constitutional His- tory, 1967: 165). Representative Rogers' position typified the combination of ra- cial attitudes and judicial ideology: Now, sir, if you pass this bill you will allow the neg- roes of this country to compete for the high office of President of the United States. Because if they are citizens at all, they come within the meaning and let- ter of the Constitution of the United States, which al- lows all natural born citizens to become candidates for the Presidency, and to exercise the duties of that of- fice if elected. [Unidentified House member]: Are you afraid of that? Mr. Rodgers: I am afraid of degrading this Government. I am afraid of danger to constitutional liberty. I am alarmed at the stupendous strides which this Congress is trying toinitiate. And I appeal in behalf of my country, in behalf of those that are to come after us, of generatins yet unborn, as well as those now living, that convservative men on the other side should rally to the standard of sovereign and independent States, and blot out this idea which is inculcutaing itself he- re, that all the powers of the States must be taken away and the power of the Czar of Russia or of the Em- peror of France must be lodged in the Federal Govern- ment. Sir, where is the civilized country on the face of the earth that gives tothe negro the right tohold the high- est office within the gift of the sovereign people, or any other office? (Virginia Commission on Constitution- al History, 1967: 167). Despite bitter debates, Civil War civil rights legislation and amendments passed. The debates clearly indicate that the Con- gressional lawmakers understood full-well the implications of their actions. They judged that they were developing laws ex- plicitely within the framework of the Constitution and Bill of Rights, and that their actions were consistent with and a logical extension of the intents of Constitutional writers. The current view of conservatives that the Fourteenth Amendment was not in- tended to apply to states (Meese, 1985) is belied by the post-War debates. John Bingham, the Ohio Representative who drafted the first section of the Fourteenth Amendment, was unequivocal in stating his intention. In an 1871 speech before the House on re- enactment of the Civil Rights Act, he explained his purpose in drafting the earlier legislation, and argued that no state ever had the right to defeat the purpose of government. In describing how he had attepted to imitate the framers of the Constitution in language and intent, he read the first eight articles of the Bill of Rights in order to specify the liberties belonging to all na- tional citizens. He then reaffirmed his intention of expanding these rights to the states: These eight articles I have shown never were limita- tions upon the power of the States, until made so by the fourteenth amendment. The words of that amendment, "no State shall make or enforce any law which shall abridge the privileges or immunities of citizens of the United States," are an express prohibition upon every State of the Union, which may be enforced under exist- ing laws of Congress, and such other laws for their better enforcement as Congress may make. . . . Sir, before the ratification of the fourteenth amend- ment, the State could deny to any citizen the right of trial byjury, and it was done. Before tht the State could abridge the freedom of the press, and it was so done in half of the States of the Union. Before that a State, as in the case of the State of Illinois, could make it a crime punishable by fine and imprisonment for any citizen within her limits, in obedience to the in- jucntin of our divine Master, to help a slave who was ready to perish; togive him shelter, or break with him his crust of bread. The vlidity of that State restric- tion uponi the rights of conscience and the duty of life was affirmed, to the shame and disgrace of Ameri- ca, in the Supreme Court of the United States; but nev- ertheless affirmed in obedience to the requirements of the Constitution. Under the Constitution as it is, not as it was, and by force of the fourteenth amendment, no State hereafter can imitate the bad example of Illinois, to which I have referred, nor can any State ever repeat the exam- ple of Georgia and send men to the penitentiary, as did that State, for teacing the Indian to read the lessons of the New Testament, to know that new evangel, "The pure in heart shall see God." Mr. Speaker, this House may safely follow the example of the makers of the Constitution and the builder of the Republic, by passing laws for enforcing allthe privileges and immunities of citizens of the United States, as guarantied by the amended Constitution and expressly enumerated in the Constitutin. Do gentlemen say that by so legislating we would strike down the rights of the State? God forbid. I believe our dual system of government essential to our national exis- tence. . . . The people of the United States are entitled to have their rights guarantied to them by the Constitution of the United States, protected by national law. I enter upon no new construction. The role of governmentis to protect the rights and interests of indi- vidual citizens, and argument that duplicated the philosophy of the writers of 1789. The passage of the civil rights acts was, then, not the outcome of hasty legislation and uninformed debate. Nor did it simply reflect a power minority imposing its will on the majority; the legislation was passed by Congress, and the Amendments were rati- fied by the requisite two-thirds of the states. Lawmakers and citizens alike were aware that they were not creating new rights nor usurping power from the states for the federal government. They fully believed, and cited appropriate law and debates from the original Constitutional Convention to substantiate their po- sition, that the Constitution was intended to protect all the liberties it specified. These amendments and legislation were sound in theory, however, but ineffective in practice. Any immediate gains of the civil rights amendments and legislation were short-lived. Although the legislation resulted in a set of legal principles that expanded rights for previoulsy excluded groups, there was no explicit ex- tra-legal machinery created to protect the rights, since it was assumed that the judicial enforcement of legislation and amend- ments would suffice for the task. This assumption was mistaken. The state courts thus continued to affirm regional social prac- tices, and the federal district courts were hesitant to review state practices; even when they did, they tended to ignore bla- tant state violations of civil rights. It would be too simplistic, however, to view the post-Civil War federal judiciary as simply affirming the states' rights doc- trine. Federal decisions in fact reflected an attempt to main- tain a delicate balance of power between states and the federal judiciary at a time when the need to re-establish political har- mony was crucial. The post-war federal judiciary was committed to maintaining and extending national power while simultaneously allowing especially the Southern states to retain a semblance of autonomy following the divisive conflicts created by the civil war. In a sense, the post-war judiciary did indeed reaffirm the in- tents of the nation's founders, but not by advocating states' rights. Congress began implement in practice George Washington's tenet that the Constitution created "one people." The process be- gan slowly, almost imperceptibly; the Nation was establishing a fundamental law for all subjects. The protections in the Consti- tution and amendments, intended by the framers to guarantee lib- erty, was--with the help of legislation and the Fourteenth Amend- ment--gradually extended to fulfill the original intents: It was forming a more perfect Union, establishing justice, promoting the general welfare, and securing the blessing of liberty to a larger body of the population. Judges also recognized that the Constitution was a living docu- ment that could be used as a political tool to balance a diversi- ty of interests, maintain social and political harmony, facili- tate growth of a rapidly growing and changing economy, and at the same time preserve federalism by strengthening its right to adju- dicate state matters. Judges also recognized that the Constitu- tion could be used as a passive instrument by denying of certiar- ori to appellants or through decisions that would preserve state practices while retaining the judicary's right to review such practices. This had the paradoxical outcome of preserving re- pressive laws while expanding judicial authority, implying that such laws could be reinterpreted at a later date. As a conse- quence, the number of petitions brought before the court by civil rights advocates, economic interests, and others, rose. But this increase of federal activity, the rise of corporate business and the expansion of federal power thorugh judicial interpretation placed a burden on the federal court which it was not able to handle (Richardson and Vines, 1970: 28). By the end of the 1870s and the re-emergence of the successionist states to grace, little attention was given to Constitutional rights, and by the next Constitutional period, the gains obtained immediately after the war were considerably diminished by Southern Black Codes, "Jim Crow" laws and federal quiescence in acting on civil rights is- sues[41]. The decline of the Republican party also reduced the impetus for enforcement of previous Republican legislation: In the election of 1874, the Republican Party lost con- trol of the House and was no longer in the position to continue the enactment of reconstruction legislation. In 1876, the Republican Party continued to lose con- gressinal seats, and the election of that year--by com- mon understanding--is considered the termantin of the reconstruction period (Virginia Commission on Constitu- tional Government, 1967: Preface). Federal power necessitated by the war was in decline, and both courts and Congress moved toward a new federal-state equilibrium. This balance was brought about by reinterpretation of law, as typified in the Civil Rights Cases (109 U.S. 3, 1883). In these cases the Court adopted a narrow interpretation of civil rights legislation and amendments, and effectively struck down the pub- lic accommodations section of the Civil Rights Act of 1875. Other post-Reconstruction decisions upheld disciminatory capital punishment based on race, the exclusion of Blacks from juries and restrictive voting practices. The Civil Rights Cases passed the political power from the federal government back to the states, and especially in the south an apartheid system became a funda- mental part of the social structure. By 1890, most Southern and some Northern states had restrictive laws against Blacks, and the civil rights legislation of the post-war decade had become inop- erative. In civil rights matters, federal courts generally avoided confrontation with, or repeal of, Southern state laws and decisions, holding to the principle that all powers not expressly given to the federal government remained with the states, regard- less of the perceived Constitutional discrepancies (Bloch, 1958: 49). A spate of decisions held that racial discrimination in em- ployment, exclusion on juries, disparate sentencing in criminal offenses and in public accommodations were either not necessarily unconstitutional or not within the domain of federal jurisdic- tion. The Slaughter-House Cases (16 Wallace 36, 1872), provide the most dramatic examples of this process. The court upheld the right of businesses to form monopolies by aplying the Fourteenth Amend- ment's Due Process Clause. The Slaughter-House Cases hold a cu- rious place in U.S. Constitutional history. On one hand, they provided a narrow interpretation of the Fourtheenth Amendment which functioned to weaken much of the Reconstruction legisla- tion. It limited the "privileges and immunities" clause of Sec- tion I, and argued: We doubt very much whether any action of a State not directed by way of discrimination against the negroes as a class, or on account of their race, will ever be held to come within the purview of this [fourteenth amendment] provision. It is so clearly a provision for that race and that emergency, that a strong case would be necessary for its application to any other. One the other hand, it had three long-range consequences for subsequent judicial theory. First, despite the apparently narrow interpretation, the decision effectively created a new category of litigants to whom the concept of due process would apply. This implicitely re-affirmed court power to bring new legal sub- jects under Constitutional protection. Second, the decision ex- panded the legal status of business by granting them the same status as "persons." The "citizenship" clause of Section I of the Fourteenth Amendment provided that "all persons born or natural- ized in the United States, and subject to the jurisdiction there- of, are citizens." By extending Constitutional protections to corporate entities, the definition of citizenship was explicitely and dramatically expanded. Hence, the inclusion of new groups to be protected by the Constitution is hardly a recent development of "activist judges." In the late nineteenth century, businesses played much the same role in expanding Constitutional legal theory as civil rights groups have done since the 1960s, and with the same result: The Law of the Land was brought in line with the times, and legal models were created by which to resolve through legal means those social problems which others forms of dispute resolution could not. Finally, the Slaughter-House Cases established one source of federal power to control private conduct (Barret and Cohen, 1985: 1016). This conservative decision by a conservative court was intended to limit federal intervention into the social sec- tor, even while expanding it in the economic realm. It had, how- ever, the ironic outcome of providing precedent for judicial in- tervention into a broad range of activities which had previously been avoided. The narrow interpretation of due process and equal protection in- tended by the Slaughter-House Cases gradually eroded. The limit- ed application of equal protection to non-Black groups estab- lished by this decision was altered. In Strauder v. West Virginia ( 100 U.S. 303, 306, 307), the Court ruled that a state statute limiting juries to whites was unconstitutional. By 1885, the Court had expanded its interpretation of the Four- teenth Amendment, and as Barrett and Cohen, 1985: 662) have ar- gued, by the mid-1880s, Chinese--and eventualy other groups--were considered to be groups entitled to its protection. Despite re- sistance to nationalization of the Fourteenth Amendment in the two decades following the Civil War, the mid-1890s, the courts had reinterpreted the Due Process Clause to guarantee rights pre- viously rejected under the Privileges and Immunities Clause in the Slaughter House Cases (Cortner, 1981: 23). Federal courts may have been cautious in their interpretion of the Constitution and federal legislation in civil rights cases, but they were far less so in other areas. Faced with the aftermath of social and economic disruption, Con- gress focused both time and resources primarily on returning the country to stability and growth. The post-civil war era had stimulated both the Northern and Southern economy, and industrial expansion in the North led to the influx of Northern capital and industrial development in the South. Territorial expansion led to rapid and dramatic growth of rail- roads and corresponding manufacturing. Such industries as coal, steel, mining and textiles flourished. After 1866, the four- teenth Amendment to the Constitution proved to be an invaluable aid to these new industries. Business not only needed the assis- tance of politicians, but also the help of the courts: Interpre- tation of the law was as important as the law itself. (Nye and Morpurgo, 1965: 584). Railroads, coal, oil and mining companies, as well as trusts benefited from litigation. Prior to civil war, businesses were small, local, and usually not incorporated. Eco- nomic necessity and technological advances transformed society from one based on labor intensive to capital intensive produc- tion. This required new laws and appropriate judicial interpre- tation to assure smooth commercial growth. Northern victory meant that Northern industrial and business interests, represent- ed by Republicans previously held in check by a coalition of Southern and northwestern interests, were free to run the nation as they wished. Federal litigation helped change this when busi- nesses began challenging state laws perceived to inhibit com- merce. The power of the economic structure on court issues and decisions continued through the close of the century. In 1886, it was "discovered" that corporations were constitution- al subjects, and thus entitled to protection under the "due pro- cess of law" clauses (Santa Clara County v. Southern Pacific Railway, 118 U.S. 394, 1886), when Chief Justice Waite declared that 14th amendment applies to "corporations" as well as persons. This represented a dramatic shift in the concept of legal rights in that non-persons now possessed rights which had previously been granted only to persons. The Due Process Clause of the fourteenth, cited by conservatives as a threat to states' rights, amendment became a convenient tool for businesses to establish and protect their rights when it served their interests. Prior to the civil war, on only two occasions did the court at- tempt to define the scope of the "due process" phrase of the fifth amendment (Barrett and Cohen, 1985: 481). After the war, changing concepts of rights, of due process, and above all, a changing society that challenged previous concepts created new social--and by extension legal--conflicts for the Court to re- solve. The first and most dramatic litigation was the "slaugh- ter-house" cases (16 Wall. 36, 1872), in which the state of Loui- sana chartered a corporation and allowed it exclusive right to conduct business in New Orleans and required all competing compa- nies to close. The statutes were challenged on the basis that they elevated the privileges of a powerful monopoly at the ex- pense of the polity in general. The plaintiffs claimed that the statutes violated the thirteenth amendment (by creating involun- tary servitude), and the fourteenth amendment (through depriva- tion of property without due process, abridging privileges and immunities of U.S. citizens, and denying plaintiffs equal protec- tion of the law). Despite an eloquent dissent by Justice Field, the court upheld the Constitutionaity of the statutes. In siding with monopolistic enterprise, the court suggested that there were areas in which the judiciary should not interfer lest it upset the balance between state and federal power. But this was not so much a states' rights issue as the reflection of a broader trend which transcended individual states. In an era of emerging monopolies, which broke down political and ideological barriers between states, this decision supported a trend that fa- cilitated the creation of a national economy along monopolistic lines, and thus contributed to the growing need for a strong cen- tral authority to maintain the production/distribution cycle of commerce. The Supreme Court further established itself as the protector of national norms in declaring bigamy illegal in Utah (Reynolds v. U.S., 98 U.S. 145, 1878). The court ruled that the state laws banning the practice did not consistute violation of freedom of religion. Writing for the majority, chief justice Morrison R. Waite argued that although religious freedom should prevail, leg- islation in the states could enact laws prescribing a rules for preservation of fundamental institutions such as marriage or fam- ily relations. While the decision may seem on its surface to up- hold the doctrine of states' rights, it actually elevated the federal judiciary as ultimate judge of national norms. The transition between the first and second Republican periods was marked by the Plessy v. Ferguson decision (163 U.S. 537, 1896). At issue was the constitutionality of racial discrimina- tion, and in upholding the practice, the decision guided state policies for the next 60 years. At issue was the constitutional- ity of an 1890 Louisiana act providing separate railway carriages for whites and blacks. The court ruled that racial separation did not necessarily stamp "the colored race with a badge of in- feriority," and created the "separate but equal" doctrine to jus- tify its position. In writing the majority opinion, Justice Brown argued that races cannot be "put on the same plane" by ju- dicial fiat: Legislation is powerless to eradicate racial instincts, or to abolish distinctions based upon physical differ- ences, and the attempt to do so can only result in ac- centuating the difficulties of the present situation. If the civil and political rights of both races be equal, one cannot be inferior to the other civilly or politically. The court did not rule that it lacked jurisdiction in such mat- ters, for it explicitely accepted that right without modifica- tion. It also created a specific doctrine, "separate but equal," to be used as a standard by which to judge future cases. The First Republican period has left an important legacy to con- temporary civil rights litigation. First, it provided the basis for intervention by the federal judiciary into private conduct. The scope of this intervention was not clearly defined, however, and subsequent decisions provided the judicial logic for expan- sion. Second, the Fourteenth Amendment was used to bring state legislation and judicial practice in line with federal norms, and thus functioned to bring a certain homogeneity to national judi- cial activity. Third, several clauses in the Fourteenth Amend- ment were reinterpreted to protect the rights of a variety of so- cial subjects that had previously been unprotected. The "citzenship," "due process," and "equal protection" clauses espe- cially were expanded to extend rights to corporations, minorities and others. It should be re-emphasized that the decisions, espe- cially those of civil rights, were often unfavorable to minori- ties. Nonetheless, the legal theories and judicial logy was fo- rulated by which the federal judiciary later justified intervention on the basis of the Fourteenth Amendment. This pro- vided the fundamental basis for subsequent intervention, which some call "judicial activism." In the next period, the courts were relatively quiet, protecting their power and consolidating the social and economic decisions to conform to the emergent cor- porate-capital phase of history. THE SECOND REPUBLICAN PERIOD (1896-1932) In the 36 years since the First Republican period, 12 new states were added to the union, and the population more than doubled from the 1860 total of 31,500,000. By 1896 the nation was still rural, but the urban poplulation was increasing rapidly. The country was in the middle of its industrial revolution--200 years after that of England--and large corporations were becoming more powerful. The Standard Oil Company had formed the first trust in 1882, and within the next few years large trusts were controlling considerable resources and power. By the 1890s, liberal thinkers judged government controlled by a privileged few who ran it for the benefit of businesses, banks railroads and large industry. In some respects, early twentieth century economic forces spurred "judicial activism" in much the same way as civil rights pres- sures did 60 years later. The growth of national industry and the need for a corresponding set of laws and regulations demanded consistent legal policies and practices, and the courts were used to challenge those laws which stifled economic freedom. Through Constitutional interpretation and enforcement, the federal judi- cary consistently voided state laws that stifled the growth of a national economy, enforced the right of contract as a Constitu- tional right, and effectively shifted power from the states to the federal government. Thus began the Progressive era in which the federal government took an increasingly prominent role in maintaining the stability and harmony of the social and economic order. William McKinley began the first of his two terms, and campaigned as an advocate of big business. During this era, the government took an aggressive role, largely at the prompting of big business and such organizations as National Association of Manufacturers and National Civil Federation, to regulate commerce and industry. The Sherman Anti-Trust Act, passed in 1890, prohibited in vague language all cominations of restraint in trade. It was largely ineffective in its first 15 years, but after the turn of the cen- tury legal issues raised by the act were beginning to reach fed- eral courts. Following the mood of the time, the Supreme Court upheld the act, further strengthening the legitimacy of judicial intervention in private affairs. Other signiicant legislation included the Federal Reserve Act and the Federal Trade Commis- sion. The former brought the nation's financial institutions un- der regulative control and thus insured stability in the economic environment The latter act, along with the Food and Drug Act and Meat Inspection act, was passd at the behest of large firms with- in each industry in order to control smaller competitors and at- tain product credibility (Greenberg, 1974: 94-95). For excel- lent discussions of the political[42] By the 1920s, the ideology of "equal opportunity" and "liberty for all" was being shattered by economic inequality, repression of socialist thought, and a political system that seemed indiffe- rent to the needs of a growing underclass. Any hope of re-estab- lishing social harmony consistent with the principles of laissez faire economic principles and a "hands-off" judicial philosophy was shattered by the Great Depression. The social conditions spawned by a changing society in chaos, and the emerging struggle for for rights afterwards, led to perhaps the most extensive le- gal changes in the nation's history. 6. LAW IN THE "MODERN ERA" The new deal brought with it profound changes between the federal government and the states, and this relationship led to the im- portance of the U.S. Supreme Court in reviewing both state and federal statutes and procedures. THE NEW DEAL ERA (1932-1968) If the second Republican period was one of mediating inter-class conflicts in the realm of commerce and industry, the New Deal era was one of mediating social conflicts created by the Great De- pression. The population continued to grow, partly because of the influx of foreign labor, and the economic structure was in- creasingly unable to accommodate a growing underclass that was unable to find secure employment and that was also excluded from fundamental liberties such as free speech and assembly, and gen- erally living on the periphery of an affluence shared by a minor- ity of the population. When the courts ruled on the constitu- tionality of laws, they consistently affirmed federal legislation controlling economic enterprise. Civil rights issues were not common, but corporate rights were nonetheless extended, and in- cluded such issues as tort, contract, interstate trade and intra- corporate regulation. In fact, Miller (1982: 165) has argued that from 1890-1937, justices read freedom of contract into the Constitution's Due Process Clauses, This dramatically altered the concept of legal rights by creating new categories of protected persons. In short, this was the era of Big Business and emerging monopoly capitalism, and the courts spend virtually no time mulling over issues of individual rights or liberty. Legislators, the judici- ary, and other social institutions were inattentive to the chang- ing social conditions, and the economic collapse of 1828 provided the opportunity for change. The ideal of equality during the Second Republican era had been dept alive by the ideal of occupa- tional mobility (Aronowitz, 1973: 154). It became increasingly clear that the ideology of opportunity was belied by the reality of class, exploitation, and general insensitivity by state and federal government to the problems of survival for an increasing portion of the population. National unemployment reached 15 mil- lion on the day of Roosevelt's inauguration (Greenberg, 1974: 105), and it became clear that the federal system, to preserve the capitalist structure, would be required to attack social ills as aggressively as it had tackled the economic ills in the Pro- gressive Era. The federal machinery that had been used to create economic regulation in the business environment was now turned upon social regulation. Thus began the new cycle of federal in- tervention in the New Deal. The marriage between big business and government was transformed with the election of President Roosevelt and the "New Deal." This period was characterized by the emergence of the "welfare state" in which the federal government began to assume responsibility for maintaining social harmony Using a variety of political and legislative strategems, President Roosevelt took an aggressive role in creating national recovery programs. His social programs especially have been criticized as "creeping socialism." These social programs in fact staved off dramatic social change by ame- lioriting the harsher conditions of the depression. Public works provided unemployed workers with at least a minimal income; wel- fare programs helped others meet daily requirements for survival. To meet the constitutional challenges to his recovery policies, Roosevelt recognized that a sympathetic judiciary was necessary, and this led to his attempt in 1937 to pack the Supreme Court with co-ideologues who would presumably rule in his favor on con- troversial cases. His bill to increase the court to 15 members, thus allowing him to appoint up to six additional justices, failed. Nonetheless, he was ultimately successful in court-pack- ing, and when he died in 1945, the only non-Roosevelt appointee was Justice Roberts, and he was soon replaced by President Tru- man. In the middle of Roosevelt's presidency, civil rights legislation re-emerged. The most important included the Fair Labor Standards Act (1938) The World War II Federal Employment Practices Commit- tee (1941, 1943), and the Wartime Voting Act (1941) which was later amended and strengthened in the Federal Voting Assistance Act (1955). In addition, much of the New Deal legislation con- tained clauses establishing the principle of non-discrimination and equality of opportunity. Well-intended as this legisation was, however, it was largely symbolic. There were no provisions for defining discrimination and no machinery for sanctioning vio- lations (BNA, 1964: 10). By the late 1930s, federal support of business had reversed and was replaced by social welfare concerns. The post-1937 Supreme Court economic decisions left intact most state and federal laws regulating economic life, and the Supreme Court consistently de- nied certiorari in cases challenging the constitutionality of such legislation (Goldman and Jahnige, 1985: 187). Despite the general support of social legislation, federal courts also upheld the constitutionality of one of the most blatant examples of ra- cism in our nation's history. In the months following the decla- ration of war with Japan, a series of executive orders, state and federal acts were passed directed against persons of Japenese de- scent, many of whom were second or third generation U.S. citi- zens. Using descent as the target category, these acts variously established curfews, restricted travel and reduced the first amendment rights of Japanese. The most controversial federal policy required relocation of large entire populations of Pacific coast Japanese to detention camps, and included confiscation of property and possessions as a practical, if not explicitely au- thorized, outcome. Although persons of German descent were not so-treated, in a series of cases in 1943 and 1944, the Supreme Court upheld the policies, arguing that persons of Japanese de- scent presented a special danger to the community in the context of the war (Hirabayashi v. U.S., 320 U.S. 81, 1943). These deci- sions were, however, overruled in Following Roosevelt's death in 1945, President Truman generally continued New Deal policy. Al- though not fully sharing the social philosophy of his predeces- sor, Truman nonetheless was committed to continuing the general thrust of Roosevelt's programs, even if not with the same enthu- siasm. Although the Roosevelt years produced no single dramatic civil rights decisions, it remains a significant period in the Consti- tutional history of civil rights for several reasons. First, and most important, it established an operative ideology of social justice--albeit in rudimentary form--by creating the rationale for protection of "the little guy." This was done through New Deal legislation, re-emergence of civil rights legislation, and above all, through translating social issues of poverty and pub- lic welfare to national policy. Second, the federal judiciary, through narrow but explicit decisions, slowly chipped away at laws that repressed individual freedom. The NAACP was particu- larly active, but other groups also sought to redress social grievances through litigation. Finally, the Supreme Court re- mained a Roosevelt court into the 1950s, thus providing a block of civil rights supporters that formed the backbone of the Warren court in the 1950s and beyond. The election of President Eisen- hower has been considered by many to represent a backlash to New Deal policies of his predecessors. This is only partially true, however, since Roosevelt's policies remained intact and continued to provide the model for federal policy for the next 15 years. President Eisenhower believed he could reverse the Court's phi- losophy when he appointed Earl Warren, a political conservative and judicial moderate, as the Court's Chief Justice in 1953. He was wrong. Driving along the nation's highways in the 1950s and 1960s, one would see sporadically-placed billboards with a three word mes- sage: "IMPEACH EARL WARREN!" In Michigan, and perhaps in other states as well, these signs were sponsored by John Birch Society sypmathizers. The sponsors, with reasoning that presaged conser- vative critics of the 1980s, argued that the Warren Court was vi- olating the Constitution and moving the country toward socialism with its radical and unfounded interpretation of the law and in- tervention into the lives of "the people." The Warren Court consolidated through judicial means the social reforms enacted by New Dealers. Almost immediately, the new Chief Justice established himself and his court as an advocate for social change. The first landmark decision, Brown v. Board of Education (347 U.S. 483, 1954) overturned Plessey v. Ferguson, and has been called the "second reconstruction" because of its profound impact on civil rights and dramatic resurrection of the rights contained in the Fourteenth Amendment. Brown was not the first case to succesfully chenge the Plessy decision, but it was the most dramatic and comprehensive. It consolidated the previ- ous decisions by making explicit the legal theories underlying Constitutional guarantees. Legal attacks on school segregation began in the 1930s, led by Black lawyers. In consistently ruling for the plaintiffs, the Supreme Court slowly chipped away at the Plessy decision, but it avoided direct confrontation with that decision until Brown. The Brown suit challenged the "separate but equal" doctrine es- tablished in the Plessy decision and was brought against the school districts of several states. The plaintiffs argued that racial segregation in public schools denied children equal pro- tection under the fourteenth amendment by denying them access to White schools which were considered superior. Although the case was originally argued in 1952, reargument was heard in 1954 be- cause a number of unanswered questions remained concerning the applicability of the fourteenth amendment to the circumstances. Writing for the majority, Chief Justice Warren wrote: Does segregation of children in public schools solely on the basis of race, even though the physical facili- ties and other "tangible" factors may be equal, deprive the children of the minority group of equal educational opportunities? We believe that it does. The Brown decision overturned Plessy, and held that using race as a criteria denied due process under the fourteenth amendment. More significantly, the decision explicitely ordered remedial ac- tion and established the federal government as the proper agent for carrying out the order. The civil rights movement began in the 1950s, and by the end of Eisenhower's second term had become a cause celebre for Blacks, white liberals and especially for politicians sensitive to the political advantages the support of this new constituency could convey. The election of John F. Kennedy in 1962 represented a re-affirmation of the New Deal and government involvement in me- diating social and political problems, and rejection of conserva- tive "hands-off" states' rights philosophy. Kennedy's New Fron- tier was in effect a series of policies aimed at garnering the support of groups previously excluded from political power. In developing programs to help minorities and the poor, Kennedy pro- vided the structure and ideology for of the civil rights movement for the next decade. The Kennedy era did not represent a reversal of the policies of previous decades; it was in fact a continuation of a trend that had waxed and waned since the 1930s. Since the 1930s, minorities had persistently litigated fourteenth amdendment issues. Blacks continued their assault on racial separatism, especially in schools and accommodations; Hispanics from the southwest chal- lenged restrictive laws barring them from full enjoyment of rights; Asians litigated against relocation and immigration; and new groups (handicapped, mentally impaired, juveniles) challenged state laws that were alleged to reduce their rights. Not all cases were equally successful, and no successful case was partic- ularly dramatic. Many cases were lost, the Supreme Court denied certiorari to many others, and even when a decision was favorable to the plaintiff, it tended to be narrow in scope. Nonetheless, the legal trends had begun under the New Deal as the courts be- came recognized as a legitimate and occasionally useful avenue to redress perceived wrongs on Constitution grounds. During the eight years of the Kennedy/Johnson administrations, broad-reaching legislation implied by Brown was enacted to pro- tect civil liberties. The most notable was the Civil Rights Act of 1964. Unlike similarly intended legislation of Roosevelt's Administration, this Act was far-reaching. It in principle banned discrimination in numerous areas, including employment, voting and public accommodations, on the basis of race, ethnici- ty, religion or sex. After three months of heated and often hos- tile debate, the law was implemented. Following the 1964 Act, several civil rights acts were passed. Among the most significant include The Housing Act of 1968, sev- eral acts prohibiting discrimination in federally-funded pro- grams, a new Voting Rights Act (1965), and the Indian Civil Rights Act (1968)[43]. It also provided the means of enforcement by creating the Equal Employment Opportunity Commission empowered with a variety of powers to redress violations. In addition, state laws restricting Bill of Rights protections to state defen- dants were being chipped away. For example, 25 states had enact- ed laws similar to the federal Civil Rights Act by 1964, although these were enforced unequally among the states. The process of expanding civil rights had begun in the 1930s, but escalated dramatically in the 1960s. Describing the expansion of protected rights risks the danger of implying that such expansion occurs in a smooth, linear manner. But legal change rarely occurs without corresponding social con- flicts. When the first civil rights revolution occurred in the 1860s, U.S. society was relatively segmented. There was no na- tional media to immediately make visible struggles for rights or to announce federal policy and decisions. Geographic mobility was limited, and groups supporting or opposing issues could not quickly descend upon a city or government agency to demonstrate on behalf of their cause. There was no history of civil disobe- dience or social activism to provide models or strategies for systematic activist involvement. This had changed by the second civil rights revolution of the mid-twentieth century. News media provided immediate information, transportation allowed mobiliza- tion of issue-oriented sympathizers, and there had emerged a va- riety of strategies for social protest. The law became a focal point around which social activists mobilized. When Rosa Parks refused to give up her seat on a Montgomery, Ala- bama, bus in 1955, she provided the symbol around which civil rights activists mobilized. Opponents of racial segregation re- sponded as early as 1956, when massive protests against the Su- preme Court ruling to desegregate schools was organized by South- ern Congressional representatives. The following year, Arkansas Governor Orval Faubus called out the national guard to prevent nine black children from entering an all-white highschool. George Wallace successfully campaigned for governor of Alabama on an explicity racist platform, Georgia Governor Lester Maddox Mad- dox stood at the door and 3,000 federal troops were called out to put down riots at the University of Mississippi when James Mere- dith became the first black ever to enroll in the school. Mere- dith was later shot to death in an ambush for his civil rights involvement. Viola Liuzzo, a white civil rights worker, was mur- dered returning from a demonstration in a crime that ultimately implicated the FBI[44]. Three civil rights workers were murdered in Mississippi in a police conspiracy in 1963 (see U.S. v. Price, 383 U.S. 787, 1966), and Martin Luther King was murdered while standing outside his Memphis motel in 1968. In addition, state and federal law enforcement agencies, along with conservative "monitoring" organizations conducted systematic surveillance, en- gaged in disruptive activity, and responded with punitive meas- ures to civil rights activists engaged in legal activities (Church Committee, 197*; Thomas, 1981). Changing technology of the post-World War two years required re- assessment of Constitutional protections against invasion unrea- sonable search and seizure, and self-incrimination. Sophisticat- ed surveillance devices, for example, have enabled law enforcement agents to listen to or view behaviors in ways never imagined by the writers of the Constitution. The Supreme Court directly confronted technological abuses in Katz v. United States (389 U.S. 347, 1967), when it reversed a 40 year old decision and precluded the use of evidence obtained from illicit wiretapping. Social norms and values transformed radically in the New Deal years, and attacks on local restrictions on literature and speech expanded the freedom of communication. The anti-communist hyste- ria of the post-war years resulted in challenges against suppres- sion of speech and assembly. Transition from corporate capital- ism to monopoly capitalism with an international character demanded new interpretions of the legal rights and status of cor- porations, of corporate law, and of tax law. A proliferation of federal agencies churned out laws, policies and regulations to monitor and administer steering strategies and thus prevent na- tional chaos. Typical of landmark civil liberties decisions are those that addressed criminal procedures and the liberties of su- spects. These included especially Mapp v. Ohio (367 U.S. 643, 1961), which expanded protection against illegal searches and/ provided the logic for the current "exclusionary rule" against use of illegally obtained evidence in criminal trials; Escobedo v. Illinois (378 U.S. 478, 1964), which/ protected the rights of suspects during interogation; and especially Miranda v. Arizona (384 U.S. 436, 1966), which held that suspects must be read their rights when an investigation/ moves to the accusatory stage, gave the Warren Court the undeserved reputation of judi- cial permissiveness and excessive activism. During this period this most important prisoner petition to that time, Gideon v. Wainwright (372 U.S. 335, 1963) was decided. Gideon, the plaintiff, was serving a sentence in Florida for breaking and entering a poolroom. Writing from his prison cell, he filed for a writ of habeas corpus, claiming that he was not represented by counsel at his state trial. He argued that he was entitled to counsel as a Constitutional right. For 30 years the nation's courts had operated on a principle established in Betts v. Brady (316 U.S. 455, 1942), which held that the concept of due process did not necessarily entitle state defendents to counsel in every non-capital case. The Gideon decision overturned Betts, and established that the right to counself was fundamental and essential to fair trials, and must be protected. This decision was far-reaching not only because of the substance of the deci- sion, but also because it provided both a model and the motiva- tion for other state prisoners to petition for writs of habeas corpus in federal court if they could identify violations of Con- stitutionally-protected rights. One federal judge has suggested that the Gideon case typifies what "prisoner litigation is all about:" You know, the most intriguing case to me that ever was filed by a prisoner was Gideon vs. Wainright . . . where an age-old practice that nobody had challenged; well, it had been challenged from time to time, but the right to a lawyer at your trial was left to the state, except in exceptional circumstances. If you couldn't speak the language, or were mentally defective, or whatever. And Gideon files this case out of Florida prison, and by God, the Supreme Court of the United States listens to it, appoints a great lawyer to repre- sent, and changes the whole rule. And that's why pris- oner cases in one sense are kind of fun, because, yes, a lot of cases lack merit, and every once in awhile you find one that's sort of a pearl that you look at and say "you know, he's put his finger on what I perceive to be a real problem (Illinois Federal Judge, 1985: personal interview). A national economy and a communication structure in which the me- dia were becoming less parochial had a homogenizing effect on the nation, and the Supreme Court became a significant mechanism for bringing local custom in line with national needs. In one sense, it is incorrect to view the judicial activism of the 1960s as a juridical revolution or as a shift to a remarkably new period in judicial philosophy. Granted, the judicial players on Supreme Court acted out the legal drama with flair, even ad-libbing when the occasion arose. But if the script of the legal play was al- tered somewhat, the genre was not. Just as West Side Story was an updated version of Romeo and Juliet, the Warren Court, with five of its members appointed by Eisenhower, two of which were later replaced by Kennedy, continued the ideological and philosophical script that had been created decades earlier. It was with relief and optimism that conservatives welcomed Richard Nixon's inaugu- ration in 1969, for it was believed that he would reverse the tide of perceived liberalism in the federal courts. Although the extension of rights became highly visible in the dawn of the War- ren court, it RETRENCHMENT: 1968 AND AFTER In the main, Goldman and Jahnige (1985: 232) are correct in argu- ing that New Deal policies begun in the 1930s ended with the election of Richard Nixon in 1968. Nixon acted quickly in an attept to shape the court to one of his liking. He had been impressed with the conservative judicial philosophy of Warren Burger, and appointed him as Supreme Court Chief Justice when Earl Warren resigned. Within his first 30 months, Nixon was able to appoint three additional justices. In his first few months in office, he also orchestrated attacks upon liberal justices who he felt were excessively liberal. In 1969, President Nixon, through Attorney general John Mitchell, prepared charges against Associate Justice Abe Fortas. Fortas was forced to resign because of earlier violations that were considered in- defensible for a Supreme Court Justice. Following the defeat of two Nixon nominees to replace Fortas, Nixon, Attorney General John Mitchell and House Republican Leader Gerald Ford joined to attack Justice William O. Douglas, considered the most-liberal of the justices. In a speech on the House floor, Ford demanded that Douglas be impeached for his unorthodox views, liberal publica- tions and life style[45]. Douglas survived the attack, but the Supreme Court became more visible in the public eye perhaps than at any previous time, and the Court lost much of its luster as a legitimate, impartial body. In some ways, the emergence of Nixon was reminiscent of Jackson's election in 1828: The country was ideologically split between na- tionalists and those of a more parochial view, and a president was elected who, it was believed, would plug the dyke and roll back the flood of federal intervention in matters considered by many to be private. President Nixon had boasted in 1968 that he would fill the federal courts with judicial conservatives to make the Constitution "more secure," and since 1969, judicial appoint- ments have included consideration of whether the candidate was "soft on crime" (Goldman, 1975: 497). Nixon appointed a Chief Justice, Warren Burger, and three associate justices to the Su- preme Court, and his successor, Gerald Ford, appointed one asso- ciate justice. The Nixon court became known as the "four plus one" court, and given that Nixon was meticulously careful about appointing co-ideologues, it was assumed that the juducial trend would be retarded, if not actually reversed. Such was not the case. If opposition to civil rights legislation and federal polices, and political intimidation of the federal judiciary were intended to influence judicial outcomes, they were unsuccessful. Although the Nixon "block of four" voted together on 54 of the 66 (82 per- cent) cases it heard in the 1972 term, none of the Warren Court decisions were overturned (Pollack, 1979: 307). The momentum of the civil rights, anti-war and other social activist movements had waned, but the impetus for change remained. Hippies and yip- pies moved from the streets and college campuses into yuppie world of law and intra-system change. The courts remained an arena for social struggle, and whatever their political ideology prior to enlistment on the bench, Supreme Court justices contin- ued to expand individual rights. In the 1970s, the court continued to affirm the New Deal and War- ren Court legacy, although with little enthusiasm. Decisions in- consistent with the legacy tended to be narrow in scope, and had little impact on reversing the civil rights trend. Roev. Wade (410 U.S. 113, 1973), which overturned as unconstitutional state legislation prohibiting abortion, symbolized the momentum of civ- il liberties. The case challenged Texas anti-abortion statutes as unConstitutional under the concept of personal liberty embod- ied in the Fourteenth Amendment's Due Process Clause, and under personal, marital, familial and sexual privacy outlined in the Bill of Rights. In writing the majority opinion, Justice Black- mun wrote: We therefore conclude that the right of personal priva- cyincludes the abortion decision, but that this right is not unqualified and must be considered against im- portant state interests. The Roe decision has been criticized for "faulty legal logic." This criticism is based on the Court's attempt to proscribe Con- stitutional guidelines for anti-abortion state laws based on a trimester concept of pre-natal life stages. Awkward as the Court's reasoning may have been, it was attempting to confront the definition of "person," a definition never specified in the Constitution. The Court was not making new law in this attempt. It was attempting to balance states' interests in protecting pre- natal life with womens' right to sexual privacy. In so-doing, the Court was faced with problems of legal definitions, medical technology which changed conceptions of "life" and Fourth Amend- ment rights by way of the Fourteenth Amendment. The decision il- lustrates the impossibility of literally application of Constitu- tional language. Despite the complaints of strict Constitutional constructionists, changes occur for which previous concepts of and method for dispute resolution are unworkable. When the judi- ciary recognizes and attempts to address these changes through interpretation of law, it is accused either of "making new law" or of rewriting the Constitution. These criticisms tend to oc- cur, however, only when decisions challenge a preferred view of social order rather than on the legal logic itself. Examination of legal logic tends to be used, as discussions of Roe vs. Wade indicate, as a rhetorical strategy to promote political ideology. This rhetorical strategy has been used frequently especially by conservatives when their appointees attempted to follow Constitu- tional ¤rather than political principles in constructing deci- sions. Civil rights advocates, however, are not immune from such criti- cisms. They, too, claimed "foul" when the Constitutional logic appeared to counter the logic of civil liberties[46]. Further, aggressive enforcement of civil rights legislation continued dur- ing the Nixon Administration, largely as the result of career civil servants retained from earlier years[47]. On the whole, rights that were previously established were consistently pro- tected, and although the trend toward expansion of rights has visibly slowed, it has not halted. This period is, it should be remembered, the one in which the rights of criminal defendants and prisoners was dramatically increased. Contrary to some views, the administration of President Carter was not a reversal of Nixon's program. As * (198*) has persua- sively argued, Carter's general political program was--if for different reasons--similar, if not identical, to that of his suc- cessor, Ronald Reagan. Carter appointed no Supreme Court justic- es and relative few (*) district or appellate judges. Carter's emphasis on civil rights did not translate into a resurgence of civil rights litigation in the courts. The civil rights litiga- tion rate (sum it). There is some evidence that his federal ap- pointees were somewhat more conservative than other democrats in deciding some liberty issues, and in fact approximated the stance of Reagan's ppointments (Suchner, Thomas and Aylward, 1986). It was under President Reagan that a direct broadside on "judi- cial activism" and civil liberties was levelled. Reagan pledged both during his first presidential campaign and after election to reverse the trend of "judicial liberalism." He delegated his At- torney General, William French Smith, the task of bringing the federal judiciary into ideological alignment with conservative principles: In October, 1981, Attorney General William French Smith launched a broadside attack on the federal courts for "subjective judicial policy-making." President Reagan, he said, would appoint new judges attuned to "the groundswell of conservatism evidenced by the 1980 elections." Mr. Reagan has done that. . . (Taylor, 1984: E5). The view persists that "judicial activism" has created excessive judicial abuses and should be reversed (Burger, 1974, 1982; Meese, 1985; Smith, 1982). Mid-way through his second term, Reagan has appointed political and judicial conservative Sandra Day O'Connor to the Supreme Court. Her appointment has created a solid conservative voting block that includes Chief Justice Burg- er and Justices Rehnquist and White. As a consequence, a single vote by a moderate judge has created the 5-4 majority required to rule against civil liberties issues. Rulings have gone particu- larly against suspects in criminal proceedings and for states rights, although there have been some pro-rights surprises in these areas. It is too early to assess the impact of current Reagan appoint- ees--especially of federal appellate judges--on civil liberties. It seems certain, however, that the attack on civil liberties will not reverse the established trend. It is also doubtful that rights once given will be readily relinquished. This ideological predilection has not, however, produced remarkable results. The philosophy underlying Burger Court decisions has, however, as Howard (1980) observed, been ad hoc. Summary Different social eras create different social isues, and this re- quires refinement, even creation, of new legal norms to replace older ones that no longer suffice to resolve conflicts or main- tain social harmony. So countervailing forces to industry power came into being---(miller, 1982: 73)---in 1860s, civil rights law; anti-trust in progressive era (bring in stuff from hist he- re); labor in 1930s, civil rights in 1960s. [Note the difference between Status rights and personal rights (Miller, 1982: 92). Status rights may conflict with personal rights, and this has im- pelled much of the response of Burger court against prior Supreme Court decisions. (Miller, 1982: 92). The use of courts in so- cial struggle has its roots in the transition to an industrial economy during the closing decades of the nineteenth century and the social transformations of the first decades of the twentieth. With the lag of about a generation between changes in the social and economic system, the Supreme Court during this period remade the Constitution in the image of Social Darwinism, supporting of the interests of big business (for an empirical discussion of Su- preme Court ideology and decisions during this period, see espe- cially Schubert, 1974). With the emergence of large, centralized industrialized bureaucracies, corporations began to acquire the status of legal subjects. This dramatically changed the concep- tion of the legal subject in that entities other than individuals became bearers of rights and privileges, and could in principle engage as "equals" in litigation. The transition from laissez faire to monopoloy capital also re- quired transformations in the legal relations governing the pro- ductive and exchange structure between corporations. Legal rela- tions were further mediated by labor struggles of the late nineteenth and early twentieth century. The outcome was an ex- pansion of rights--albeit in asymetrical balance--for individu- als, corporations (which acquired and strengthened their subject status) and the state itself (as it acquired increasing legal power and authority by which to intervene in mediating social ex- istence). Although this increased subject status conferred a va- riety of rights, it also implied obligations in that legal sub- jects such as corporations and government agencies, became potential targets for litigation, thus creating a new avenue for resolving social conflict under federal laws. CONCLUSION The purpose of this manuscript has been to illustrate the manner in which a variety of social forces have guided the development of the content and application of law over the centuries. The emergence of law as a social practice began at least 3,000 years ago, and has changed in response to new social conditions. The laws of Hammurabi were not appropriate for more complex societies such as Greece or Rome. Mosaic law was fine for a relatively un- complex and homogeneous society, but it was not appropriate for a society that required meeting the needs of diverse groups. The legal principles of England, although still with us today, were practiced much differently, primarily because the nature of Eng- lish society was much different than the one in which we current- ly live. The laws of the post-Civil War era were likewise modi- fied, because the industrialization and emergence of new social groups had different needs than existed prior to the Civil War. What does this tell us about the relationship between law and so- ciety today? It demonstrates that law changes in response to so- cial conditions, and that legal principles can be interpreted-- correctly--to meet the changing social conditions. The meaning of the Fourteenth Amendment, for example, has changed largely be- cause new groups have demanded equal protection, and the princi- ples embodied in the Fourteenth Amendment provided the logic, but not necessarily the explicit provisions, to meet them. Hence, when we speak of "legal fundamentalism" or a "doctrine of origi- nal intents," we must first understand the role of law in socie- ty, how law changes, and above all, the different intents of con- stitutional principles. The Constitution, as a document of compromise, was, above all, a set of guidelines for reconciling diverse interests and goals, not an exact blueprint to be liter- ally followed to the letter. Footnotes [1] My own view is that legal fundamentalism is a political, not a judicial, ideology. This would make a good paper topic. [2] In some ways, this system was similar to the logic of civil law, in which offenders are expected to pay compensation and penalties. In blood feuds, the wrong was "corrected," and a bit more tacked on as punishment. This, on occasion, perpet- uated a feud, especially when the offender's family felt too much vengeance had been extracted, and retaliation was re- quired. [3] Feudalism was the dominant form of social organization during the Middle Ages. The term "medieval" as used here is synony- mous with "Middle Ages," and refers roughly to a period be- tween the fall of the Roman Empire (fifth century A.D.) and the Renaissance (fifteenth century A.D.). Feudalism has been called an invention of historians (Bean, 1968: 1) in that the concept itself was not used until the nineteenth century. Customary historical usage defines feudalism consistent with the root meaning of feudum, namely, a designation of the mil- itary obligations required in return for holding a portion of land. It is especially these obligations and their corre- sponding social relations that formed the bulk of civil law through the Middle Ages. Wallerstein's definition is pre- ferred as the most descriptive. [4] "suitors," Suitors were the owners of property and the elect- ed men of the hundreds (or townships). By the eleventh cen- tury, much of England was divided into shires, except where Danish influence prevailed, and each shire was divided into small units known as hundreds for fiscal purposes. The hun- dred was both a territorial division and a court, and as Holdsworth (1956: 7) has argued they were also a form of de facto police organization. The hundred court was the judi- cial unit for ordinary affairs and met every four weeks, while the county court was appointed to be held twice a year (Pollack and Maitland, 1968: 42). [5] The witan was a feature of European administration and refers to a body elected or appointed to advise the king. Oleson (1955: 110) contends that the term "witenagemot" has no broader technical meaning other than as a meeting of the wi- tan. [6] The concept of the king's peace did not originally apply to all subjects, but was limited to protect the king in his house and travels. A violation was an act of personal dis- obedience toward the king, much more serious than a breach of simple public order. After the Normans, however, the concept rapidly expanded and was used as a general rule by which to maintain public order. [7] The continental practice of trial by combat was not used un- til the Normans, and the customary procedure in English tri- als was the oath, a system in which a defendant was required to have a designated number of "oath helpers" swear to his or her character. In the oath system, which became popularized especially after the twelfth century, the district's reputa- ble men who were presumed to know the facts of the case were summoned to pronounce on oath the truth of the matter, thus deciding the case (Poole, 1964: 406). Failing the oath, the ordeal, usually of hot water or iron, was employed to deter- mine the verdict. (Barlow, 1972: 51). [8] although Edward's reign was marked by a struggle for power between natives and foreigners, primarily French (Oleson, 1955: 5). it tends to be forgotten that William's claim to the throne was based in part from his English ancestry, and the close relationship between England and Normandy during this period. There is also strong evidence that Edward the Confessor himself favored Duke William as his successor. Rather than a major watershed in English history, the so- called Norman conquest was a more or less typical violent transition, and not the first time a foreigner had been an English King. [9] These custom-based procedural importations included trial by ordeal and combat, which the Normans preferred as a means of resolving disputes. The theory behind this process was "di- vine intervention," although its use in England has probably been overstated. They also had inherited a tradition of use of the Carolingian missi dominici and of the sworn investiga- tion, which they reshaped (Barlow, 1972: 107). Barlow (1972: 107) has reminded us, however, that although Norman law was French in origin, it was shaped according to provincial cus- tom and had never been committed to writing. The Normans al- so introduced trial by combat; however in the Norman system, the defendant had the explicit right to refuse combat, al- though the defendant might then face trial by ordeal. [10] That he ruled for over a decade may be due in part to his counsellors, especially Anselm, Abbot of Bec, who suggested that William 1) recognize the harshness of his rule, 2) for- give the debts due him, 3) restore the laws of the Confes- sor, 4) reduce his ministers' oppression of the populace, and 5) redress the wrongs of the Church (Davis, 1957: 89). [11] A functional equivalent of this body had existed for several centuries, and it slowly became a formal and departmental- ized institution and an effective organ of Norman and Angev- in administration. Under Edward the Confessor, this body was the witan, but under the Normans became the Curia Regis. In addition to its judicial role, it kept careful records of all cases which came before it, thus providing a written legacy for subsequent generations. As Poole (1964: 11) has observed, it was, at least through the eleventh century, a court essentially feudal in character comprising high-rank- ing persons and bishops who sat as barons. It was a tribu- nal of loyal supporters, but nonetheless a court that at- tempted, for the time, to administer law systematically. In the eleventh century, the curia Regis were those assemblies that met with the king three times annually and performed judicial tasks. Under Henry II, it began taking shape as a strong, central court which later produced the court of Com- mon Pleas. The advice of this body, even in its infancy, could not be ignored, for without the material support of the participants, the king could not carry out his policy (Poole, 1964: 11). [12] Ecclesiastical law remained more rational than English law. Under canon law, the rules of evidence were balanced in fa- vor of the defendant. There were two stages to an ecclesi- astical evidentiary proceeding: In the first, the evidence brought by the accuser was marshalled and sifted; secondly, if the evidence was regarded as inconclusive, the accused had the right of clearing himself by the oath of compurgators. The law of evidence, as understood by the Church, was compara- tively scientific, and many accusations which the untu- tored common sense of a lay judge would have regarded as completely proven were rejected as baseless in the courts-Christian (Davis, 1957: 208). [13] This expansion of administration is analogous to our contem- porary judicial response to overload in which Chief Justice Berger, rather than transfer power outside the judiciary, has recommended new inferior courts, under jurisdiction of the U.S.S.C., be created to process additional cases. [14] Forest law, which governed the vast extent of the king's do- mains, was bound neither by Norman legal forms nor by Eng- lish traditions, but was framed absolutely at the king's will. These forest laws were later to become a key focus of class struggle, symbolizing the diverse interests of a vari- ety of groups (see Thompson, 1975). [15] Members of this body were actually nobles, but were called justices when they assumed their new position. [16] The Athenian jury was more a forum than a trial, and trials with several thousand "jurors" were not uncommon. Unlike its later English distant cousin, the Athenians did not rely on evidence, witnesses, or "rules of fairness." Although ju- ries derived from statute law, the procedures did not. Most scholars also agree that the jury was not a novelty in the twelfth century. It had been employed in primitive form in Anglo-Saxon England and, on the continent, by the Carolingi- an emperors in the ninth century before passing to the Nor- mans. [17] For an excellent discussion of this aspect of law and jus- tice in the twelfth century, see especially Poole, 1964:385-424. [18] An assize referred to a convening body, and the laws enacted at such sittings were referred to as "assizes." The title of a particular assize generally took the name of the location in which this body sat. [19] Henry attempted to put in writing those limitations on the clergy that had previously been custom, and he attempted to force the bishops to commit themselves publicly to obey crown authority. The Pope, normally predisposed toward Hen- ry, rejected these constitutions and sided with Becket, who rejected the king's attempt to explicitly subordinate the Church. It was this assize particularly which illustrated the independence of archbishop Thomas Becket, Henry's close friend, from his former mentor. Although Henry carefully modified his proposals when confronted with opposition from the church (and Becket, prior to his murder), these consti- tutions for the first time in English history created a code of laws issued by the sole authority of the king, without any appeal to the sanction of binding and immutable custom (Green, 1968: 128). [20] As Rembar (1980: 20) has observed, appeal originally re- ferred to a criminal proceeding brought by a private citi- zen, the practice of appeal and indictment existed side by side. Appeal tended to culminate in a jury trial. It was not until several centuries later that the meaning of appeal as judicial review of legislation or litigation became com- mon. [21] The Church withdrew the sanction of its authority from all forms of ordeal by 1215, but even prior to this there was decreasing confidence in its validity (Warren, 1973: 321). [22] John sought Papal intervention, not as King of England, but as Papal servant and bearer of Christianity, and he con- vinced the Pope that the Magna Carta threatened the Cru- sades. [23] Although the Magna Carta extended the rights of men, it was not so generous in recognizing the rights of women. Chapter 34, for example, explicitly strengthened their subservient social status: "No one shall be seized nor imprisoned on the appeal of a woman concerning the death of any one except her husband." [24] The term Parliament came into use in the mid-thirteenth cen- tury, but the barons who met at Runnymede, despite their ap- parent lack of representation from shires and boroughs, were labeled retrospectively Parliamentum Runimedae (Maitland, 1913: 72). [25] This contributed to the rise in the popularity and power of the court of equity in the chancery: because of the hardening and definition of the Common Law, because of the decline of the personal monarch and the continued delegation of his function, including even some of his prerogative powers, and because of the unsettled times, the chancery emerged unmistakably as a great court of equitable jurisdiction, with power, precedents, and procedures of its own (Wilkinson, 1964: 266). [26] An analysis of the political and ideological impact of the Inns of Court on law and the judiciary remains to be done. One one suspects it was substantial, given the conflicts be- tween the nobility and crown, and their joint opposition to the church. [27] This was the period of the Carrier Case (1473), a landmark in theft law. In this case, a person who had been assigned responsibility for transporting bales had taken the contents for personal use, and was apprehended and charged with a felony. Under the laws of the period, a person who came le- gally into possession of an object was not considered guilty for converting it for personal gain, and this incident, al- though it may seem odd in the hindsight of legal history, nonetheless required considerable debate and new interpreta- tion of the law by which felonious theft was defined. [28] Although the Star Chamber was referred to in the fourteenth century (Holdsworth, 1956: 496), its origins are considered by most historians to be more recent. Consensus holds that it took the form by which we know it primarily under Henry VII and the name was taken from the shape of the room in which it met. It was under Henry VIII and Elizabeth, how- ever, that its character as an abusive, powerful body was shaped. Its significance was not so much judicial as polit- ical, for it operated beyond the reach of local terrorism and was empowered not only to issue writs of subpoena but also to examine defendants upon oath. It dealt with a broad range of offenses, and its jurisdiction stretched to include nobility who had been previously exempt from ordinary tribu- nals (Fisher, 1913: 21). [29] Public trials, explicit procedural rules, emphasis on the state being required to prove the case, and relative freedom to speak in court distinguished English from European trials at this time. [30] This was the period of Thomas More's UTOPIA (1516), in which he described a mythical society in which there were few laws and no lawyers. [31] For an excellent review of and response to doctrinaire states' rights advocates and critics of Constitutional ac- tivism, see especially Miller, 1982. [32] For a brief but excellent history of English common law in the colonies, see especially Reinsch, 1968. [33] The decline of Puritanism occurred partially through inter- nal schisms between commercial and agrarian interests, and partly because of competing challenges from non-Puritans. Perhaps the most significant reason for the decline of Puri- tanism lay in its doctrine: It was always a difficult creed to hold, containing seemingly irreconcilable principles which had to be kept in alignment by constant argument and adjustment. Its concepts of God, free will, knowledge and revela- tion, sin, and moral duty were maintained throughout the seventeenth century in delicate intellectual and imaginative balance; to later generations of ministers and laity they seemed les capable of proof or reconcil- iation. As the concepts themselves came under the scrutiny of a rationalistic, hard-headed age, the sys- tem they supported disintegrated. . .(Russell and Mor- purgo, 1965: 345). [34] The first major restrictive act was the Navigation Act (1660), which regulated colonial commerce in order to expand English trade. A century later, the Sugar Act (1764), the Stamp Act (1765), the Townshend Acts (1767) and the "Intol- erable Acts (1774) prompted overt opposition to the Crown's legal authority and created fertile ground for resistance to English legal and political authority. Had the Crown taken a less restrictive policy toward the Colonies, it is unlike- ly the rebellious merchants would have found sufficient sup- port for their cause. [35] For a sympathetic but nonetheless highly critical evaluation of Beard, see especially Brown, 1965. See also the work of Alfred A. Young, of NIU, in In These Times, Vol. 11, #34, Sept 9-15: 12-13. [36] The term "radical Republican" did not mean that this group shared the political philosophy of what has become known as "leftists." The advocacy of minority rights to which this group adhered was not motivated by broad philosophic con- cerns, but by political expediency. In the areas of com- merce, individual rights and other issues, they were not significantly distinguishable from their colleagues. [37] Collins (1974/1912: 7-12) has argued that the primary rea- sons for the passage of the Fourteenth Amendment were polit- ical. While acknowledging racial equality as one motivating factor, he adds that other functions included punishing the South, expanding and centralizing the power of the federal government, and enhancing control of the Republican party. [38] There were three other sections in the fourteenth amendment, none bearing on civil rights. The second section specified that representative apportionment in Congress would be pro- portionate to state population; the third disallowed persons taking part in "insurrection or rebellion against the United States" from serving as federal officials except by two- thirds vote of Congress; the fourth removed federal and state liability for or debts incurred through the civil war. The final section provided Congress with the "power to en- force, by appropriate legislation, the provisions of this article." [39] The following states were excluded: Alabama, Arkansas, Flo- rida, Georgia, Louisiana, Mississippi, North Carolina, South Carolina, Tennessee, Texas and Virginia. By 1868, seven of the confederate states were re-admitted to the Union, and Texas, Virginia and Mississippi were re-instated during the Grant administration after they had endorsed the fifteenthh Amendment and Black sufferage. [40] The Congressional debates on civil liberties legislation and amendments between 1849-1876 have been reprinted by the Vir- ginia Commission on Constitutional History, 1867. [41] Jim Crow laws were laws specifically intended to maintain racial segregation by placing restrictions on interracial marriage, voting, ownership of property, employment, resi- dence, use of public accommodations and education. They functioned as current Apartheid law does in contemporary South Africa. [42] economy of the Reform Era, 1890-1948, see especially Green- berg, 1974; Kokol, 19**; Weinstein, 19**; Chandler, 1972, and Aronowitz, 1973). [43] The best summary of federal civil rights legislation and corresponding legal cases affirming them is probably Antieau (1980). [44] Gary Rowe, an FBI informant, was implicated in the 1965 mur- der. A subsequent civil suit alleged that the FBI new of the danger to Ms. Liuzzo's saftey, but failed to take pro- tective action (Peterson, 1983). [45] Ford apparently had misgivings about his involvment in the affair, and later suggested that he had been "had" by his colleagues (Pollack, 1979: 299). [46] Two examples of this include Bakke v. *, (* v. * ), in which the court ruled in favor of merit qualifications for admis- sion to a California medical school, and in *, in which the Court ruled in favor of laying-off municipal workers on the basis of seniority rather than minority preference. The Constitutional logic of both cases was sound, and there is no evidence that either case had any impact on subsequent civil liberties cases. [47] For an excellent discussion of federal application of civil rights policies, see especially U.S. Commission on Civil Rights, 1976). BIBLIOGRAPHY Bibliography available on request
<--Return to Jim Thomas's homepage